首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
     


Happiness and virtue in Socrates' moral theory
Authors:Gregory Vlastos
Affiliation:(1) Dept. of Philosophy, University of California, 94720 Berkeley, CA, U.S.A.
Abstract:Conclusion In Section IV above we start with texts whose prima facie import speaks so strongly for the Identity Thesis that any interpretation which stops short of it looks like a shabby, timorous, thesis-saving move. What else could Socrates mean when he declares with such conviction that lsquono evilrsquo can come to a good man (T19), that his prosecutors lsquocould not harmrsquo him (T16(a)), that if a man has not been made more unjust he has not been harmed (T20), that lsquoall of happiness is in culture and justicersquo (T16(a)), that living well is lsquothe samersquo as living justly (T15)? But then doubts begin to creep in. Recalling that inflation of the quantifier is normal and innocuous in common speech (ldquothat job means everything to him, he'll do anything to get it, will stick at nothingrdquo) we ask if there is really no chance at all that lsquono evilrsquo in T19, lsquonot harmedrsquo in T20 might be meant in the same way? The shift from lsquono harmrsquo at T16(a) to lsquono great harmrsquo at T16(b), once noticed, strengthens the doubt. It gets further impetus in T21(b) when to explain how lsquoall of happiness is in culture and justicersquo he depicts a relation (that recurs more elaborately in T22) which, though still enormously strong, is not quite as strong as would be required by identity. The doubt seeps into T15 when we note that current usage did allow just that relation as a respectable use of lsquothe samersquo.At that point we begin to wonder if resort to the Identity Thesis might not be just a first approximation to a subtler, more finely nuanced, doctrine which would give Socrates as sound a foundation for what we know he wants to maintain at all costs - the Sovereignty of Virtue - without obliterating the eudaemonic value of everything else in his world. We cast about for a credible model of such a relation of virtue to happiness and hit on that multicomponent pattern sketched on p. 9 above. We ascertain that this will afford a comprehensively coherent eudaemonist theory of rational action, while its rival would not, and will fit perfectly a flock of texts in Section V which the latter will not fit at all. Are we not entitled to conclude that this is our best guide to the true relation of virtue to happiness in Socrates' thought - the one for which he would have declared if he had formulated explicitly those two alternative theses and made a reasoned choice between them?The lsquoSocratesrsquo of this paper is the protagonist of Plato's earlier dialogues. I list these (by self-explanatory abbreviations), borrowed from T. Irwin, Plato's Moral Theory [1974] (hereafter lsquoPMTrsquo): Ap., Ch., Cr., Eud., Eu., G., HMa., HMi, Ion, La., Ly., Pr., R., I. I assume, but shall not argue here, that in this segment of his corpus, Plato aims to recreate the doctrines and arguments of his teacher in dramatic scenes, all of which (except for the Ap.) may be, and most of which undoubtedly are, fictional; I shall be referring these works, under this proviso, as Plato's lsquoSocratic dialoguesrsquo. (I did not include the Menexenus in the above list, since the parody of a funeral oration in this dialogue is implicitly dissociated from Socrates.)
Keywords:
本文献已被 SpringerLink 等数据库收录!
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号