首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   6155篇
  免费   107篇
  国内免费   5篇
  2023年   20篇
  2022年   23篇
  2021年   24篇
  2020年   33篇
  2019年   48篇
  2018年   180篇
  2017年   164篇
  2016年   251篇
  2015年   135篇
  2014年   79篇
  2013年   252篇
  2012年   344篇
  2011年   304篇
  2010年   78篇
  2009年   69篇
  2008年   87篇
  2007年   104篇
  2006年   104篇
  2005年   1354篇
  2004年   702篇
  2003年   497篇
  2002年   183篇
  2001年   57篇
  2000年   46篇
  1999年   51篇
  1998年   30篇
  1997年   24篇
  1994年   22篇
  1992年   42篇
  1991年   49篇
  1990年   68篇
  1989年   53篇
  1988年   38篇
  1987年   54篇
  1986年   43篇
  1985年   39篇
  1984年   37篇
  1983年   27篇
  1979年   41篇
  1976年   18篇
  1975年   37篇
  1974年   38篇
  1973年   39篇
  1972年   31篇
  1971年   35篇
  1970年   29篇
  1969年   29篇
  1968年   26篇
  1967年   30篇
  1966年   28篇
排序方式: 共有6267条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
F R?tzer 《Psyche》1987,41(8):717-725
  相似文献   
3.
Adult age differences in the consistency effect were examined in 3 experiments. The consistency effect refers to items inconsistent with expectations being better remembered than items consistent with expectations. Younger and older adults walked into an office room and viewed objects that varied in their consistency with expectation. Immediate and delayed recognition tests on item information (i.e., distractors were defined by their semantic identity) revealed that both age groups recognized unexpected items better than expected items. However, when recognition of token information was requested (i.e., distractors were defined by their physical appearance), younger adults, in contrast to older adults, exhibited consistency effects. Also, under divided attention, young adults revealed the same pattern of data as did elderly adults under full attention. The results are discussed in terms of capacity-related differences in distinctive encoding.  相似文献   
4.
5.
We report an eye movement experiment investigating the influence of the focus operator only on syntactic processing of "long" relative clause sentences. Paterson, Liversedge, and Underwood (1999) found that readers were garden pathed by "short" reduced relative clause sentences containing the focus operator only . They argued that due to thematic differences between "short" and "long" relative clause sentences, garden path effect might not occur when "long" reduced relative clause sentences are read. Eye-tracking data show that garden path effects found during initial processing of the disambiguating verb of "long" reduced sentences without only were absent or delayed in the case of counterparts with only . We discuss our results in terms of current theories of sentence processing.  相似文献   
6.
7.
Despite widespread use the cognitive demands of the five-disc Tower of London (TOL) are unknown. Research suggests that conflict moves (those that are essential to the solution but do not place a disc in its final position) are a key aspect of performance. These were examined in three studies via a verification paradigm, in which normal participants were asked to decide whether a demonstrated move was correct. Experiment 1 showed that individual move latencies increase with the number of intermediate moves until the disc is placed in its goal position (resolution). Post hoc tests suggested that the number of alternative moves and moves to resolve a disc were independent predictors of performance. Experiment 2 successfully manipulated these factors in an experimental design. Experiment 3 showed that they remain determinants of performance as familiarity increased. Overall, errors on the task were significantly correlated with spatial memory. The implications of these findings for the use of the TOLin cognitive psychology and as an assessment tool are discussed.  相似文献   
8.
9.
10.
Robertson  Simon 《Synthese》2010,181(1):81-106

What is the relation between what we ought to do, on the one hand, and our epistemic access to the ought-giving facts, on the other? In assessing this, it is common to distinguish ‘objective’ from ‘subjective’ oughts. Very roughly, on the objectivist conception what an agent ought to do is determined by ought-giving facts in such a way that does not depend on the agent’s beliefs about, or epistemic access to, those facts; whereas on the subjectivist conception, what an agent ought to do depends on his beliefs. This paper defends the need for, and explicates, a third category of ‘ought’: ‘warranted oughts’. Section 1 introduces the distinction between objective and subjective ‘oughts’. Sections 2–3 draw attention to some serious problems with each. Section 4 examines, though rejects, a recent attempt to replace subjective ‘oughts’ with objective ‘wide-scope oughts’ operating on belief-action combinations. Section 5 explicates the notion of a warranted ‘ought’ and defends the account against some possible objections. The resulting a picture is one in which an adequate analysis of practical normativity requires both objective and warranted ‘oughts’. Section 6 concludes by responding to a worry about countenancing both.

  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号