全文获取类型
收费全文 | 4171篇 |
免费 | 370篇 |
国内免费 | 75篇 |
专业分类
4616篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 9篇 |
2024年 | 66篇 |
2023年 | 90篇 |
2022年 | 73篇 |
2021年 | 97篇 |
2020年 | 209篇 |
2019年 | 231篇 |
2018年 | 216篇 |
2017年 | 202篇 |
2016年 | 211篇 |
2015年 | 141篇 |
2014年 | 215篇 |
2013年 | 607篇 |
2012年 | 166篇 |
2011年 | 146篇 |
2010年 | 125篇 |
2009年 | 176篇 |
2008年 | 197篇 |
2007年 | 220篇 |
2006年 | 151篇 |
2005年 | 175篇 |
2004年 | 146篇 |
2003年 | 117篇 |
2002年 | 93篇 |
2001年 | 52篇 |
2000年 | 69篇 |
1999年 | 38篇 |
1998年 | 29篇 |
1997年 | 26篇 |
1996年 | 24篇 |
1995年 | 23篇 |
1994年 | 16篇 |
1993年 | 18篇 |
1992年 | 9篇 |
1991年 | 9篇 |
1989年 | 6篇 |
1988年 | 9篇 |
1985年 | 20篇 |
1984年 | 15篇 |
1983年 | 14篇 |
1982年 | 13篇 |
1981年 | 23篇 |
1980年 | 13篇 |
1979年 | 15篇 |
1978年 | 18篇 |
1977年 | 19篇 |
1976年 | 9篇 |
1975年 | 19篇 |
1974年 | 8篇 |
1973年 | 12篇 |
排序方式: 共有4616条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
181.
Edmund Wall 《Philosophia》2008,36(2):237-249
182.
Negative self-focused cognitions mediate the effect of trait social anxiety on state anxiety 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
The cognitive model of social anxiety predicts that negative self-focused cognitions increase anxiety when anticipating social threat. To test this prediction, 36 individuals were asked to anticipate and perform a public-speaking task. During anticipation, negative self-focused cognitions or relaxation were experimentally induced while self-reported anxiety, autonomic arousal (heart rate, heart rate variability, skin conductance level), and acoustic eye-blink startle response were assessed. As predicted, negative self-focused cognitions mediated the effects of trait social anxiety on self-reported anxiety and heart rate variability during negative anticipation. Furthermore, trait social anxiety predicted increased startle amplitudes. These findings support a central assumption of the cognitive model of social anxiety. 相似文献
183.
184.
运用情景模拟和角色扮演的方法,研究大学生对网瘾和作弊的责任归因结构及其应对策略。对416名被试的研究结果显示:(1)责任归因的心理结构是一个“责任推断→责任情感→责任行为”的一元结构模式。(2)我国大学生的责任推断过程与维纳的经典理论基本一致,但在行为应对策略上存在一定的文化差异。(3)大学生对网瘾和作弊的责任推断倾向明显并与情感体验基本保持一致,但与行为应对策略存在一定的冲突。(4)大学生在网瘾和作弊的责任推断、情感体验以及应对策略上存在一定差异。 相似文献
185.
HIROSHI NONAMI 《The Japanese psychological research》2008,50(1):24-35
Abstract: The present study investigated the social determinants required to stimulate consistency in minority members' attitudes and behavior. The experiment was designed to examine the consistency of individuals in the context of an intergroup belief cross wherein the majority belief (or minority) in a categorical in-group shifted to the minority (or majority) in the out-group. The results indicated that the members of a majority within an in-group consistently preserved their behavioral intentions and beliefs even though they were positioned as a minority within an out-group. That is, the minority members in the whole intergroup context maintained consistency diachronically as a result of support from the majority of their in-group. The theoretical implications on the consistency of minority members, such as whistle-blowers in companies, are discussed. 相似文献
186.
Past research on the accuracy of personality judgments has largely focused on person perception scenarios that are public in nature (e.g., face-to-face interactions, personal websites). This study investigated the accuracy of personality judgments on the basis of highly private information: a person’s natural stream of thought. Nine naïve judges rated the personality of 90 targets on the basis of their 20-min stream-of-consciousness essays. Judges’ level of accuracy was significant and substantial for all Big Five dimensions. The substantial and relatively uniform accuracy across all Big Five dimensions suggests that a person’s moment-to-moment thoughts provide good information for the accurate judgment of personality in general rather than specific diagnostic information for the accurate judgment of private traits such as Neuroticism. 相似文献
187.
Donald Capps 《Journal of religion and health》2008,47(4):560-576
In four earlier articles, I focused on the theme of the relationship of melancholia and the mother, and suggested that the
melancholic self may experience humor (Capps, 2007a), play (Capps, 2008a), dreams (Capps, 2007c), and art (Capps, 2008b) as restorative resources. I argued that Erik H. Erikson found these resources to be valuable remedies for his own melancholic
condition, which had its origins in the fact that he was illegitimate and was raised solely by his mother until he was three years
old, when she remarried. In this article, I focus on two themes in Freud’s Leonardo da Vinci and a memory of his childhood (1964): Leonardo’s relationship with his mother in early childhood and his inhibitions as an artist. I relate these two themes
to Erikson’s own early childhood and his failure to achieve his goal as an aspiring artist in his early twenties. The article
concludes with a discussion of Erikson’s frustrated aspirations to become an artist and his emphasis, in his psychoanalytic
work, on children’s play.
Donald Capps is Professor of Pastoral Psychology at Princeton Theological Seminary. His books include Men, Religion, and
Melancholia (1997), Freud and Freudians on Religion (2001), and Men and Their Religion: Honor, Hope, and Humor 相似文献
188.
Brian Hill 《Studia Logica》2008,89(1):81-109
It is well-known that classical models of belief are not realistic representations of human doxastic capacity; equally, models
of actions involving beliefs, such as decisions based on beliefs, or changes of beliefs, suffer from a similar inaccuracies.
In this paper, a general framework is presented which permits a more realistic modelling both of instantaneous states of belief,
and of the operations involving them. This framework is motivated by some of the inadequacies of existing models, which it
overcomes, whilst retaining technical rigour in so far as it relies on known, natural logical and mathematical notions. The
companion paper (Towards a “sophisticated” model of belief dynamics. Part II) contains an application of this framework to the particular case of belief revision.
Presented by Hannes Leitgeb 相似文献
189.
Kevin McCain 《Synthese》2008,164(2):185-200
Although several important methodologies implicitly assume the truth of epistemic conservatism, the view that holding a belief
confers some measure of justification on the belief, recent criticisms have led some to conclude that epistemic conservatism
is an implausible view. That conclusion is mistaken. In this article, I propose a new formulation of epistemic conservatism
that is not susceptible to the criticisms leveled at earlier formulations of epistemic conservatism. In addition to withstanding
these criticisms, this formulation of epistemic conservatism has several benefits. First, this formulation has the benefits
of earlier formulations of epistemic conservatism, that is to say it makes sense of our intuitions about justification in
regard to both memory beliefs and beliefs for which we have forgotten our evidence. Second, it provides a good way of responding
to the skeptic’s challenge concerning the possibility of possessing knowledge of the external world posed by the Alternative
Hypotheses argument. Third, it provides responses to both forms of a new skeptical problem plaguing basic knowledge structure
theories, the Problem of Easy Knowledge formulated by Stewart Cohen. I argue that given the many benefits of this formulation
of epistemic conservatism and the fact that it is not vulnerable to the criticisms that undermine earlier formulations of
epistemic conservatism, this formulation of epistemic conservatism is a plausible view to maintain. 相似文献
190.
Moral phenomenology is (roughly) the study of those features of occurrent mental states with moral significance which are
accessible through direct introspection, whether or not such states possess phenomenal character – a what-it-is-likeness.
In this paper, as the title indicates, we introduce and make prefatory remarks about moral phenomenology and its significance
for ethics. After providing a brief taxonomy of types of moral experience, we proceed to consider questions about the commonality within and distinctiveness of such experiences, with an eye on some of the main philosophical issues in ethics and how moral phenomenology might be brought
to bear on them. In discussing such matters, we consider some of the doubts about moral phenomenology and its value to ethics
that are brought up by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Michael Gill in their contributions to this issue.
相似文献
Mark Timmons (Corresponding author)Email: |