全文获取类型
收费全文 | 297篇 |
免费 | 7篇 |
专业分类
304篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 5篇 |
2021年 | 3篇 |
2020年 | 8篇 |
2019年 | 18篇 |
2018年 | 11篇 |
2017年 | 13篇 |
2016年 | 6篇 |
2015年 | 9篇 |
2014年 | 8篇 |
2013年 | 26篇 |
2012年 | 5篇 |
2011年 | 4篇 |
2009年 | 11篇 |
2008年 | 11篇 |
2007年 | 18篇 |
2006年 | 20篇 |
2005年 | 19篇 |
2004年 | 11篇 |
2003年 | 14篇 |
2002年 | 15篇 |
2001年 | 14篇 |
2000年 | 15篇 |
1999年 | 5篇 |
1998年 | 8篇 |
1997年 | 5篇 |
1996年 | 3篇 |
1995年 | 5篇 |
1994年 | 3篇 |
1992年 | 3篇 |
1991年 | 1篇 |
1990年 | 4篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1986年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有304条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
131.
The aim of this paper is to prove strong completeness theorems for several Anderson-like variants of Gödels theory wrt. classes of modal structures, in which: (i). 1st order terms order receive only rigid extensions in the constant objectual 1st order domain; (ii). 2nd order terms receive non-rigid extensions in preselected world-relative objectual domains of 2nd order and rigid intensions in the constant conceptual 2nd order domain. 相似文献
132.
Kuczewski M 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》1998,19(6):509-524
Casuistry and principlism are two of the leading contenders to be considered the methodology of bioethics. These methods may be incommensurable since the former emphasizes the examination of cases while the latter focuses on moral principles. Conversely, since both analyze cases in terms of mid-level principles, there is hope that these methods may be reconcilable or complementary. I analyze the role of principles in each and thereby show that these theories are virtually identical when interpreted in a certain light. That is, if the gaps in each method are filled by a concept of judgment or Aristotelian practical wisdom, these methods converge. 相似文献
133.
Robert T. Craig 《Argumentation》1996,10(4):461-474
This essay explores the dialectics of theory and practice in terms of argumentation theory. Adapting Jonsen and Toulmin's (1988) notion of a Theory-Practice spectrum, it conceives Theory and Practice as extreme ends of a continuum and discourses as falling at various points along the continuum. Every theoritical discourse has essential practical aspects, and every practical discourse has essential theoretical aspects. Practices are theorized to varying degrees but every practice is thorized to some degree. Reflective discourse, which is discourse about practice, moves to and fro along the Theory-Practice continuum. Reflective discourse involves argumentation. Practical argumentation connects theory to practice; it appeals to general warrants, which may be simple or may tap into elaborate conceptual structures, in order to establish grounds for practical judgments. A practical discipline is a relatively coherent intellectual-professional enterprise that cultivates a field of social practice by engaging within itself and with practitioners in a reflective discourse. The argumentation of a practical discipline, like ordinary practical reflection, moves to and fro along the Theory-Practice continuum but in more methodical steps informed by systematic methodological reflection on the reflective process itself. 相似文献
134.
实践美学视野中的自然鉴赏观 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Keping Wang 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》2007,2(1):140-149
Appreciating nature may at its best feature have three levels of experience according to practical aesthetics. The first level
is more sensuous as it largely pleases the ear and eye, the second level is more psychological as it chiefly pleases the mind
and mood, and the third level is more sublimate as it mainly pleases the will and spirit. In Chinese culture the affinity
between man and nature can be traced back to the traditional conception of tian ren he yi 天人合一 as heaven-human oneness, which will be ultimately conducive to the artistic realm or aesthetic state of being.
This paper was delivered at the XVI International Congress of Aesthetics on “Changes in Aesthetics” held during 18–23 July
2004 in Rio De Janiero, Brazil. 相似文献
135.
136.
This paper contains five observations concerning the intended meaning of the intuitionistic logical constants: (1) if the explanations of this meaning are to be based on a non-decidable concept, that concept should not be that of `proof"; (2) Kreisel"s explanations using extra clauses can be significantly simplified; (3) the impredicativity of the definition of can be easily and safely ameliorated; (4) the definition of in terms of `proofs from premises" results in a loss of the inductive character of the definitions of and and (5) the same occurs with the definition of in terms of `proofs with free variables". 相似文献
137.
Contact relations have been studied in the context of qualitative geometry and physics since the early 1920s, and have recently received attention in qualitative spatial reasoning. In this paper, we present a sound and complete proof system in the style of Rasiowa and Sikorski (1963) for relation algebras generated by a contact relation. 相似文献
138.
Martin Sticker 《British Journal for the History of Philosophy》2013,21(5):976-989
Ido Geiger's paper ‘What it is the Use of the Universal Law Formula of the Categorical Imperative?’ is part of a growing trend in Kant scholarship, which stresses the significance of the rational competence of ordinary human beings. I argue that this approach needs to take into account that the common agent is an active reasoner who has the means to find out what she ought to do. The purpose of my paper is to show how universality already figures in the active reasoning of pre-theoretical agents in the form of a common universalization test. I present textual evidence for this test, and argue that this conception does not present pre-theoretical moral cognition in an overly intellectualistic or mechanistic way. Finally, I discuss how, on the pre-theoretical level, universalization relates to humanity or a rational agent's special status. Universalization is present to common agents in the form of procedures or questions that we ask ourselves, humanity as an awareness of certain particularly blatant violations of duty. These two different modes of cognition of duty are reflected in two different formulae of the Categorical Imperative. 相似文献
139.
JOHN BROOME 《Theoria》2009,75(2):79-99
I develop a scheme for the explanation of rational action. I start from a scheme that may be attributed to Thomas Nagel in The Possibility of Altruism, and develop it step by step to arrive at a sharper and more accurate scheme. The development includes a progressive refinement of the notion of motivation. I end by explaining the role of reasoning within the scheme. 相似文献
140.
by Elizabeth Corey 《Zygon》2009,44(1):139-151
Michael Oakeshott's religious view of the world stands behind much of his political and philosophical writing. In this essay I first discuss Oakeshott's view of religion and the mode of practice in his own terms. I attempt next to illuminate his idea of religion by describing it in less technical language, drawing upon other thinkers such as Georg Simmel and George Santayana, who share similar views. I then evaluate Oakeshott's view as a whole, considering whether his ideas about religion can stand up to careful scrutiny and whether they have value for present-day reflection on religion. 相似文献