排序方式: 共有103条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
81.
Wouter H. Slob 《Argumentation》2002,16(2):179-196
Deductivism is not merely a logical technique, but also a theory of normativity: it provides an objective and universal standard of evaluation. Contemporary dialectical logic rejects deductive normativity, replacing its universal standard by an intersubjective standard. It is argued in this paper that dialectical normativity does not improve upon deductive normativity. A dialogico-rhetorical alternative is proposed. 相似文献
82.
83.
Grace Helton 《No?s (Detroit, Mich.)》2020,54(3):501-526
I develop and defend the view that subjects are necessarily psychologically able to revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence. Specifically, subjects can revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence, given their current psychological mechanisms and skills. If a subject lacks this ability, then the mental state in question is not a belief, though it may be some other kind of cognitive attitude, such as a supposition, an entertained thought, or a pretense. The result is a moderately revisionary view of belief: while most mental states we thought were beliefs are beliefs, some mental states which we thought were beliefs are not beliefs. The argument for this view draws on two key claims: First, subjects are rationally obligated to revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence. Second, if some subject is rationally obligated to revise one of her mental states, then that subject can revise that mental state, given her current psychological mechanisms and skills. Along the way to defending these claims, I argue that rational obligations can govern activities which reflect on one's rational character, whether or not those activities are under one's voluntary control. I also show how the relevant version of epistemic ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ survives an objection which plagues other variants of the principle. 相似文献
84.
Murat BaÇ 《Journal for General Philosophy of Science》2000,31(1):39-56
In the end of the nineteenth century, there was a remarkable ‘empiricist attitude’ found among certain philosopher-scientists,
an attitude which arguably emerged in the main as a reaction to the anti-scientific mood prevalent in the culture that time.
Those philosopher-scientists, such as Mach and Hertz, were particularly anxious to emphasize and laud the privileged status
of the empirical dimension ofour scientific knowledge, distinguishing it carefully from the theoretical constructions and
hypothetical entities that are ordinarily posited by scientists. Yet, as I exhibit in this article, there were certain crucial
philosophical differences between these two thinkers with respect to their general conception of scientific theories and scientific norms
guiding the activity. I suggest further that the most central difference in this context between Mach and Hertz can justifiably
(and, perhaps, more fruitfully) be articulated and reckoned in traditional andcontemporary epistemological terms.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
85.
The anti-metaphysical intentions of naturalism can be respected without abandoning the project of a normative epistemology.
The central assumptions of naturalism imply that (1.) the distinction between action and behaviour is spurious, and (2.) epistemology
cannot continue to be a normative project. Difficulties with the second implication have been adressed by Normative Naturalism,
but without violating the naturalistic consensus, it can only appreciate means-end-rationality. However, this does not suffice
to justify its own implicit normative pretensions. According to our diagnosis, naturalism succumbs to the lure of an absolute
observer's stance and thereby neglects the need for participation in communal practice. By contrast, methodical culturalism
ties down the concepts of epistemology to the success of such practice. Only from this perspective, the normative force of
epistemology can be appreciated. Also, the mind-body problem loosens its hold and the distinction between action and behaviour
is reestablished. In the last section, the mutual relation between philosophy andscience is reconsidered.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
86.
Stephanie Leary 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2017,95(3):529-542
Many meta-ethicists are alethists: they claim that practical considerations can constitute normative reasons for action, but not for belief. But the alethist owes us an account of the relevant difference between action and belief, which thereby explains this normative difference. Here, I argue that two salient strategies for discharging this burden fail. According to the first strategy, the relevant difference between action and belief is that truth is the constitutive standard of correctness for belief, but not for action, while according to the second strategy, it is that practical considerations can constitute motivating reasons for action, but not for belief. But the former claim only shifts the alethist's explanatory burden, and the latter claim is wrong—we can believe for practical reasons. Until the alethist can offer a better account, then, I argue that we should accept that there are practical reasons for belief. 相似文献
87.
This is a contribution to the symposium on Tim Scanlon’s Being Realistic about Reasons (2014). We have two aims here: First, we ask for more details about Scanlon’s meta-metaphysical view (about his notion of a domain, his criterion of existence, his ambition to remain ontologically thin, and on the role of pragmatic considerations in Scanlon’s picture), showing problems with salient clarifications. And second, we raise independent objections to the view – to its explanatory productivity, its distinctness, and the argumentative support it enjoys. 相似文献
88.
Wybo Houkes 《Journal for General Philosophy of Science》2002,33(2):251-267
In this paper, I review Quine's response to the normativity charge against naturalized epistemology. On this charge, Quine's
naturalized epistemology neglects the essential normativity of the traditional theory of knowledge and hence cannot count
as its successor. According to Quine, normativity is retained in naturalism as ‘the technology of truth-seeking’. I first
disambiguate Quine's naturalism into three programs of increasing strength and clarify the strongest program by means of the
so-called Epistemic Skinner Box. Then, I investigate two ways in which the appeal to technology as normative enterprise can
be made good. I argue that neither coheres with other aspects of Quine's philosophy, most notably the elimination of intentionality.
Finally, I briefly consider a third reconstruction of the response, which involves an extension of the web of “belief” to
practical know-how. I conclude that the normativity of Quine's (strong) naturalism cannot be found in the technology of truth-seeking.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
89.
Stephen Ingram 《Inquiry (Oslo, Norway)》2018,61(7):649-669
Some philosophers object to moral error theory by arguing that there a parity between moral and epistemic normativity. They maintain that moral and epistemic error theory stand or fall together, that epistemic error theory falls, and that moral error theory thus falls too. This paper offers a response to this objection on behalf of moral error theorists. I defend the view that moral and epistemic error theory do not stand or fall together by arguing that moral error theory can be sustained alongside epistemic expressivism. This unusual combination of theories can be underpinned by differences in the foundational norms that guide moral and epistemic inquiry. I conclude that the problem of epistemic normativity fails to show that it is compulsory for us to reject moral error theory. 相似文献
90.
David Horst 《European Journal of Philosophy》2017,25(1):47-67
An enkratic agent is someone who intends to do A because she believes she should do A. Being enkratic is usually understood as something rationality requires of you. However, we must distinguish between different conceptions of enkratic rationality. According to a fairly common view, enkratic rationality is solely a normative requirement on agency: it tells us how agents should think and act. However, I shall argue that this normativist conception of enkratic rationality faces serious difficulties: it makes it a mystery how an agent's thinking and acting can be guided by the enkratic requirement, which, as I shall further argue, is something that an adequate conception of enkratic rationality must be able to explain. This, I suggest, motivates exploring a different account of enkratic rationality. On this view, enkratic rationality is primarily a constitutive requirement on agency: it is a standard internal to agency, i.e., a standard that partly spells out what it is to exercise one's agential powers well. 相似文献