全文获取类型
收费全文 | 1502篇 |
免费 | 131篇 |
国内免费 | 51篇 |
专业分类
1684篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 10篇 |
2024年 | 31篇 |
2023年 | 43篇 |
2022年 | 35篇 |
2021年 | 38篇 |
2020年 | 82篇 |
2019年 | 109篇 |
2018年 | 96篇 |
2017年 | 94篇 |
2016年 | 94篇 |
2015年 | 52篇 |
2014年 | 71篇 |
2013年 | 184篇 |
2012年 | 44篇 |
2011年 | 30篇 |
2010年 | 25篇 |
2009年 | 37篇 |
2008年 | 49篇 |
2007年 | 72篇 |
2006年 | 83篇 |
2005年 | 72篇 |
2004年 | 66篇 |
2003年 | 66篇 |
2002年 | 40篇 |
2001年 | 21篇 |
2000年 | 27篇 |
1999年 | 31篇 |
1998年 | 19篇 |
1997年 | 12篇 |
1996年 | 10篇 |
1995年 | 13篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 8篇 |
1992年 | 3篇 |
1991年 | 1篇 |
1990年 | 4篇 |
1989年 | 1篇 |
1988年 | 8篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
1980年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有1684条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
31.
Yuri Alexandrov Olga Svarnik Irina Znamenskaya Marina Kolbeneva Karina Arutyunova Andrey Krylov Alexandra Bulava Brian Feldman 《The Journal of analytical psychology》2020,65(3):476-496
As shown in our previous paper (‘Regression I. Experimental approaches to regression’, JAP, 65, 2, 345-65), the common mechanism of regression can be described as reversible dedifferentiation, which is understood as a relative increase of the proportion of low-differentiated (older) systems in actualized experience. Experimental data show that regression following disease (chronic tension headache) is followed by adaptation and an increase in system differentiation in that experience domain which contains systems responsible for that adaptation. The results of mathematical modelling support the idea that reversible dedifferentiation can be one of the mechanisms for increasing the effectiveness of adaptation through learning. Reversible dedifferentiation, which is phenomenologically described as regression, is a general mechanism for restructuring the organism-environment interactions in situations where behaviours that were effective in the past become ineffective. Reversible dedifferentiation has evolved as a component of adaptation when new behaviours are formed and large-scale modifications in the existing behaviours are required in the face of changes in the external and/or internal environment. Thus, the authors believe that this article provides evidence for Jung’s view that regression is not only a ‘return’ to past forms of thinking, affects and behaviour, but that regressive processes provide a significant impetus for psychological growth and development. 相似文献
32.
Julie N. Y. Zhu;Long W. Lam;Yolanda Na Li;Maggie Q. Shao; 《Journal of Occupational & Organizational Psychology》2024,97(4):1550-1571
Pro-group unethical behaviour (PGUB) refers to a set of behaviours that conflict with moral standards but are beneficial to the interests of an actor's workgroup. Drawing on social cognitive theory, this research investigates whether, how, and when perceived co-worker PGUB leads employees to engage in the same unethical behaviour. We propose that moral disengagement is a crucial mechanism through which PGUB is transmitted from co-workers to employees and that this relationship is further amplified by employees' group identification. The results of three field studies featuring different samples consistently highlight the mediating role of moral disengagement in the relationship between perceived co-worker PGUB and employee PGUB. Furthermore, employees who identify strongly with their workgroup are more likely to exhibit moral disengagement and learn their co-workers' PGUB than are employees with low group identification. The findings of this research provide insights for both theory and practice. 相似文献
33.
Forge J 《Science and engineering ethics》2004,10(3):531-542
I ask whether weapons research is ever justified. Weapons research is identified as the business of the engineer. It is argued
that the engineer has responsibility for the uses to which the tools that he designs can be put, and that responsibility extends
to the use of weapons. It is maintained that there are no inherently defensive weapons, and hence there is no such thing as
‘defensive’ weapons research. The issue then is what responsibilities as a professional the engineer has in regard to such
research. An account is given to ground the injunction not to provide the means to harm as a duty for the engineers. This
account is not, however, absolutist, and as such it allows justifiable exceptions. The answer to my question is thus not that
weapons research is never justified but there must be a strong assurance that the results will only be used as a just means
in a just cause. 相似文献
34.
Ton van den Beld 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》2001,4(4):383-399
What I set out to do is to cast some doubt on the thesis that, in Bernard Williams's words, any appeal to God in morality either adds nothing at all, or it adds the wrong sort of thing. A first conclusion is that a morality of real, inescapable and (sometimes) for the agent costly obligations, while being at home in a theistic metaphysic, does not sit easily with metaphysical, atheistic naturalism. The second conclusion is that Christine Korsgaard's impressive ethical project which is neutral towards theism and atheism fails in giving a satisfying account of such obligations. My final claim is that a theistic account in terms of a strong divine command theory might succeed where non- and atheistic accounts seem to founder. 相似文献
35.
Eric Mack 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》1999,2(2):87-115
This paper offers a programmatic philosophical articulation of moral and political individualism. This individualism consists of two main components: value individualism and rights individualism. The former is the view that, for each individual, the end which is of ultimate value is his own well-being. Each individual's well-being has ultimate agent-relative value and the only ultimate values are these agent-relative values. The latter view is that individuals possess moral jurisdiction over themselves, i.e., rights of self-ownership. These rights (along with other rights individuals may come to possess) constrain the manner in which agents may pursue value. For this reason, the articulated individualism is an constrained individualism. Sketches of arguments are offered for both value and rights individualism. And it is argued that the sole legitimate function of legal/political institutions is to further delineate and protect the rights of individuals. However, the paper is also concerned to indicate why this radical moral and political individualism does not have many of the features or implications that are commonly ascribed to it. In this connection, I seek to show how this social doctrine accords with individuals' having concern for the well-being of others, with the emergence of relationships among individuals that have both instrumental and non-instrumental value, with a degree of responsibility for self and others that is often thought to be antithetical to individualism and, in general, with a flourishing of civil order. 相似文献
36.
Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》1999,2(2):135-147
What makes killing morally wrong? And what makes killing morally worse than letting die? Standard answers to these two questions presuppose that killing someone involves shortening that person's life. Yet, as I argue in the first two sections of this article, this presupposition is false: Life-prolonging killings are conceivable. In the last two sections of the article, I explore the significance of the conceivability of such killings for various discussions of the two questions just mentioned. In particular, I show why the conceivability of life-prolonging killings renders Frances M. Kamm's attempt to provide an answer to the second question problematic. 相似文献
37.
Peter van Inwagen 《The Journal of Ethics》1999,3(4):343-351
In his classic paper, The Principle of Alternate Possibilities, Harry Frankfurt presented counterexamples to the principle named in his title: A person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise. He went on to argue that the falsity of the Principle of Alternate Possibilities (PAP) implied that the debate between the compatibilists and the incompatibilists (as regards determinism and the ability to do otherwise) did not have the significance that both parties had attributed to it -- since moral responsibility could exist even if no one was able to do otherwise. I have argued that even if PAP is false, there are other principles that imply that moral responsibility entails the ability to do otherwise, and that these principles are immune to Frankfurt-style counterexamples. Frankfurt has attempted to show that my arguments for this conclusion fail. This paper is a rejoinder to that reply; I argue that he has failed to show this. 相似文献
38.
Abner Shimony 《Zygon》1988,23(3):333-340
Abstract. Criticisms are presented against Eger's challenge to the demarcation between the natural sciences and ethics. Arguments are given both against his endorsement of the "new" philosophy of science and against his rejection of the fact-value dichotomy. However, his educational recommendations are reinforced rather than weakened by these criticisms 相似文献
39.
Neal Judisch 《The Journal of Ethics》2007,11(4):357-375
John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza offer a theory of moral responsibility which makes responsibility dependent upon the
way in which moral agents view themselves. According to the theory, agents are responsible for their actions only if they
think of themselves as apt candidates for praise and blame; if they come to believe they are not apt candidates for praise
and blame, they are ipso facto not morally responsible. In what follows, I show that Fischer and Ravizza’s account of responsibility for consequences is
inconsistent with this subjective element of their theory, and that the subjective element may be retained only if they are
willing to implausibly restrict their account of responsibility for consequences. I end by discussing the broad significance
of the failure of the subjective element for their overall approach to moral responsibility. 相似文献
40.
Qiyong Guo 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》2007,2(3):345-362
Mou Zongsan uses the highest moral principle “autonomy” to interpret Confucius’ benevolence and Mencius’ “inherent benevolence
and righteousness”, focuses on the self-rule of the will. It does not do any harm to Mencius’ learning, on the contrary, it
is conducive to the communication between Chinese and Western philosophies. If we stick to Kant’s moral self autonomy and
apply it to interpreting Zhu Xi’s moral theory, similarly we will discover the implications of Zhu Xi’s “autonomy” in his
moral learning. Therefore, it is inappropriate for Mou Zongsan to say that Zhu Xi’s ethics belongs to the autonomous one.
__________
Translated from Zhexue Yanjiu 哲学研究 (Philosophical Researches), 2005, (6): 33–39 相似文献