全文获取类型
收费全文 | 560篇 |
免费 | 17篇 |
国内免费 | 1篇 |
专业分类
578篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 7篇 |
2023年 | 11篇 |
2022年 | 2篇 |
2021年 | 7篇 |
2020年 | 12篇 |
2019年 | 26篇 |
2018年 | 14篇 |
2017年 | 25篇 |
2016年 | 30篇 |
2015年 | 18篇 |
2014年 | 19篇 |
2013年 | 74篇 |
2012年 | 14篇 |
2011年 | 8篇 |
2010年 | 11篇 |
2009年 | 24篇 |
2008年 | 21篇 |
2007年 | 30篇 |
2006年 | 28篇 |
2005年 | 22篇 |
2004年 | 20篇 |
2003年 | 32篇 |
2002年 | 19篇 |
2001年 | 12篇 |
2000年 | 19篇 |
1999年 | 16篇 |
1998年 | 5篇 |
1997年 | 13篇 |
1996年 | 5篇 |
1995年 | 8篇 |
1994年 | 9篇 |
1993年 | 1篇 |
1992年 | 3篇 |
1991年 | 5篇 |
1990年 | 1篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 4篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有578条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
101.
Jiaming Chen 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》2008,3(1):67-82
Whether empirical givenness has the reliability that foundationalists expect is a point about which some philosophers are
highly skeptical. Sellars took the doctrine of givenness as a “myth,” denying the existence of immediate perceptual experience.
The arguments in contemporary Western epistemology are concentrated on whether sensory experience has conceptual contents,
and whether there is any logical relationship between perceptions and beliefs. In fact, once the elements of words and conceptions
in empirical perception are affirmed, the logical relationship between perceptual experience and empirical belief is also
affirmed. This relationship takes place through perceptual experience acting as evidence for beliefs. The real problem lies
in how one should distinguish between the different relationships with perception of singular beliefs and of universal beliefs,
and in how singular beliefs can provide justification for universal beliefs.
__________
Translated from Zhongguo Shehui Kexue 中国社会科学 (Social Sciences in China), 2007, (1): 65–75 相似文献
102.
Gero Schwenk 《Journal for General Philosophy of Science》2006,37(1):99-110
Summary The topic of this article is the analysis of the relations between different levels of reality. The core argument is based on considerations of both an epistemology of action and manipulative causality as a criterion of object identity. The argumentation is extended towards the concepts of self-organization and self-regulation. Finally, several views on reduction and the problems of emergence and complexity are discussed. 相似文献
103.
Christopher Hoyt 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2007,61(1):39-49
It is well understood that Wittgenstein defends religious faith against positivistic criticisms on the grounds of its logical independence. But exactly how are we to understand the nature of that independence? Most scholars take Wittgenstein to equate language-games with belief-systems, and thus to assert that religions are logical schemes founded on their own basic beliefs and principles of inference. By contrast, I argue that on Wittgenstein’s view, to have religious faith is to hold fast to a certain picture of the world according to which one orients one’s actions and attitudes, possibly even in dogmatic defiance of contrary evidence. Commitment to such a picture is grounded in passion, not intellection, and systematic coherence is largely irrelevant. 相似文献
104.
Ernest Sosa 《Philosophical Studies》2009,144(1):107-109
This is a summary of A Virtue Epistemology, the book that is the subject of this book symposium. 相似文献
105.
Matthew William McKeon 《Synthese》2009,167(1):163-182
An account of validity that makes what is invalid conditional on how many individuals there are is what I call a conditional
account of validity. Here I defend conditional accounts against a criticism derived from Etchemendy’s well-known criticism
of the model-theoretic analysis of validity. The criticism is essentially that knowledge of the size of the universe is non-logical
and so by making knowledge of the extension of validity depend on knowledge of how many individuals there are, conditional
accounts fail to reflect that the former knowledge is basic, i.e., independent of knowledge derived from other sciences. Appealing
to Russell’s pre-Principia logic, I defend conditional accounts against this criticism by sketching a rationale for thinking
that there are infinitely many logical objects. 相似文献
106.
107.
Jan Woleński 《Studia Logica》2007,86(3):479-497
This paper proposes a formal framework for the cognitive relation understood as an ordered pair with the cognitive subject
and object of cognition as its members. The cognitive subject is represented as consisting of a language, conequence relation
and a stock of accepted theories, and the object as a model of those theories. This language allows a simple formulation of
the realism/anti-realism controversy. In particular, Tarski’s undefinability theorem gives a philosophical argument for realism
in epistemology.
Special Issue Formal Epistemology II. Edited by Branden Fitelson 相似文献
108.
Guy Axtell 《Synthese》2007,158(3):363-383
This essay extends my side of a discussion begun earlier with Duncan Pritchard, the recent author of Epistemic Luck.Pritchard’s work contributes significantly to improving the “diagnostic appeal” of a neo-Moorean philosophical response to
radical scepticism. While agreeing with Pritchard in many respects, the paper questions the need for his concession to the
sceptic that the neo-Moorean is capable at best of recovering “‘brute’ externalist knowledge”. The paper discusses and directly
responds to a dilemma that Pritchard poses for virtue epistemologies (VE). It also takes issue with Pritchard’s “merely safety-based”
alternative. Ultimately, however, the criticisms made here of Pritchard’s dilemma and its underlying contrast of “anti-luck”
and “virtue” epistemologies are intended to help realize his own aspirations for a better diagnosis of radical scepticism
to inform a still better neo-Moorean response. 相似文献
109.
循证医学的兴起被认为是医学界重要的现代化运动,其哲学基础却一直倍受质疑。回顾了循证医学概念的发展和基本假设,整理了从认识论视角质疑循证医学的若干观点,着重介绍循证医学倡导者对循证医学认识论的基本看法,包括证据和知识的关系,观察到的、可观察的和不可观察的事实间的关系,正确地进行观察,指出循证医学不是全新的医学证据产生与运用理论,而是对多种科学推理规则的综合运用。循证医学是应客观需要而产生,因争议而不断自我完善,实现其迅速发展。 相似文献
110.
Michael Morreau 《Studia Logica》1996,57(1):47-71
Sir David Ross introduced prima facie duties, or acts with a tendency to be duties proper. He also spoke of general prima facie principles, wwhich attribute to acts having some feature the tendency to be a duty proper. Like Utilitarians from Mill to Hare, he saw a role for such principles in the epistemology of duty: in the process by means of which, in any given situation, a moral code can help us to find out what we ought to do.After formalizing general prima facie principles as universally quantified conditionals I will show how seeming duties can be detached from them. There will be examples involving lies, burnt offerings and the question of whether to have a napkin on your lap while eating asparagus. They will illustrate the defeasibility of this detachment, how it can lead into dilemmas, and how general prima facie principles are overridden by more specific ones.I've been lucky to discuss parts of this project with among others Jeff Horty, Paul McNamara, Alasdair MacIntyre, Wlodek Rabinowicz and Michael Slote. Thanks, too, to Henry Prakken and the reviewers for Studia Logica 相似文献