全文获取类型
收费全文 | 390篇 |
免费 | 3篇 |
国内免费 | 3篇 |
专业分类
396篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 2篇 |
2024年 | 8篇 |
2023年 | 13篇 |
2022年 | 5篇 |
2021年 | 8篇 |
2020年 | 23篇 |
2019年 | 30篇 |
2018年 | 23篇 |
2017年 | 29篇 |
2016年 | 27篇 |
2015年 | 24篇 |
2014年 | 20篇 |
2013年 | 44篇 |
2012年 | 20篇 |
2011年 | 4篇 |
2010年 | 6篇 |
2009年 | 13篇 |
2008年 | 4篇 |
2007年 | 5篇 |
2006年 | 9篇 |
2005年 | 9篇 |
2004年 | 5篇 |
2003年 | 19篇 |
2002年 | 13篇 |
2001年 | 6篇 |
2000年 | 3篇 |
1999年 | 8篇 |
1998年 | 2篇 |
1997年 | 3篇 |
1996年 | 1篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 2篇 |
1992年 | 1篇 |
1991年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 3篇 |
排序方式: 共有396条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
341.
Kristie Miller 《Inquiry (Oslo, Norway)》2018,61(3):223-251
It was once held to be a virtue of the growing block theory that it combines temporal dynamism with a straightforward account of in virtue of what past-tensed propositions are true, and an explanation for why some future-tensed propositions are not true (assuming they are not). This put the growing block theory ahead of its principal dynamist rival: presentism. Recently, new growing block theorists have suggested that what makes true, past-tensed propositions, is not the same kind of thing as what makes true, present-tensed propositions. They have done so in an attempt to defuse a particular epistemic objection to their view. In this paper it is argued that the new growing block theorist faces a dilemma. The more unified a strategy is for responding to the epistemic objection, the more that strategy results in the new growing block model positing truthmakers that are similar to those posited by the presentist, which erodes the purported advantage of the growing block theory over presentism. On the other hand, versions of the new growing block theory that embrace disunified strategies are better able to differentiate themselves from presentism, but are unattractive because of their disunity. 相似文献
342.
Stephen Ingram 《Inquiry (Oslo, Norway)》2018,61(7):649-669
Some philosophers object to moral error theory by arguing that there a parity between moral and epistemic normativity. They maintain that moral and epistemic error theory stand or fall together, that epistemic error theory falls, and that moral error theory thus falls too. This paper offers a response to this objection on behalf of moral error theorists. I defend the view that moral and epistemic error theory do not stand or fall together by arguing that moral error theory can be sustained alongside epistemic expressivism. This unusual combination of theories can be underpinned by differences in the foundational norms that guide moral and epistemic inquiry. I conclude that the problem of epistemic normativity fails to show that it is compulsory for us to reject moral error theory. 相似文献
343.
Disputes about theory in bioethics almost invariablyrevolve around different understandings of morality or practicalreasoning; I here suggest that the field would do well to becomemore explicitly contentious about knowledge, and start the taskof putting together a clinical epistemology. By way of providingsome motivation for such a discussion, I consider two cases ofresistance to shifts in clinical practice that are, by and large,not ethically controversial, highlighting how differentconceptions of epistemic authority may contribute to clinicians'unwillingness to adopt these changes, and sketching out someinitial suggestions for epistemic analysis of clinical practice. 相似文献
344.
J. Ritola 《Argumentation》2001,15(3):295-312
This paper criticizes Kent Wilson's (`Circular Arguments', 1988) arguments against the analysis of the fallacy of begging the question in epistemic terms and against the division of the fallacy into equivalence and dependency types. It is argued that Wilson does not succeed in showing that the epistemic attitude to the fallacy analysis should be given up. Further, it is argued that Wilson's arguments against the division of the fallacy into two types can be overcome by altering the accounts he criticizes (David Sanford (1971, 1984, 1988) and John Biro (1977, 1984)): fallacy analysis should concentrate on externalized arguments, but this does not mean that either the epistemic attitude or the dependency conception should be given up. 相似文献
345.
346.
Murat BaÇ 《Journal for General Philosophy of Science》2000,31(1):39-56
In the end of the nineteenth century, there was a remarkable ‘empiricist attitude’ found among certain philosopher-scientists,
an attitude which arguably emerged in the main as a reaction to the anti-scientific mood prevalent in the culture that time.
Those philosopher-scientists, such as Mach and Hertz, were particularly anxious to emphasize and laud the privileged status
of the empirical dimension ofour scientific knowledge, distinguishing it carefully from the theoretical constructions and
hypothetical entities that are ordinarily posited by scientists. Yet, as I exhibit in this article, there were certain crucial
philosophical differences between these two thinkers with respect to their general conception of scientific theories and scientific norms
guiding the activity. I suggest further that the most central difference in this context between Mach and Hertz can justifiably
(and, perhaps, more fruitfully) be articulated and reckoned in traditional andcontemporary epistemological terms.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
347.
The anti-metaphysical intentions of naturalism can be respected without abandoning the project of a normative epistemology.
The central assumptions of naturalism imply that (1.) the distinction between action and behaviour is spurious, and (2.) epistemology
cannot continue to be a normative project. Difficulties with the second implication have been adressed by Normative Naturalism,
but without violating the naturalistic consensus, it can only appreciate means-end-rationality. However, this does not suffice
to justify its own implicit normative pretensions. According to our diagnosis, naturalism succumbs to the lure of an absolute
observer's stance and thereby neglects the need for participation in communal practice. By contrast, methodical culturalism
ties down the concepts of epistemology to the success of such practice. Only from this perspective, the normative force of
epistemology can be appreciated. Also, the mind-body problem loosens its hold and the distinction between action and behaviour
is reestablished. In the last section, the mutual relation between philosophy andscience is reconsidered.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
348.
Many powerful logics exist today for reasoning about multi-agent systems, but in most of these it is hard to reason about an infinite or indeterminate number of agents. Also the naming schemes used in the logics often lack expressiveness to name agents in an intuitive way.To obtain a more expressive language for multi-agent reasoning and a better naming scheme for agents, we introduce a family of logics called term-modal logics. A main feature of our logics is the use of modal operators indexed by the terms of the logics. Thus, one can quantify over variables occurring in modal operators. In term-modal logics agents can be represented by terms, and knowledge of agents is expressed with formulas within the scope of modal operators.This gives us a flexible and uniform language for reasoning about the agents themselves and their knowledge. This article gives examples of the expressiveness of the languages and provides sequent-style and tableau-based proof systems for the logics. Furthermore we give proofs of soundness and completeness with respect to the possible world semantics. 相似文献
349.
Christopher Cowie 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2016,94(1):115-130
Moral error theories are often rejected by appeal to ‘companions in guilt’ arguments. The most popular form of companions in guilt argument takes epistemic reasons for belief as a ‘companion’ and proceeds by analogy. I show that this strategy fails. I claim that the companions in guilt theorist must understand epistemic reasons as evidential support relations if her argument is to be dialectically effective. I then present a dilemma. Either epistemic reasons are evidential support relations or they are not. If they are not, then the companions in guilt argument fails. If they are, then a reduction of epistemic reasons to evidential support relations becomes available and, consequently, epistemic reasons cease to be a viable ‘companion’ for moral reasons. I recommend this structure of argument over existing strategies within the literature and defend my claims against recent objections from companions in guilt theorists. 相似文献
350.
André J. Abath 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2013,91(3):593-597
It is held by many philosophers that it is a consequence of epistemic contextualism that speakers are typically semantically blind, that is, typically unaware of the propositions semantically expressed by knowledge attributions. In his ‘Contextualism, Invariantism and Semantic Blindness’ (this journal, 2009), Martin Montminy argues that semantic blindness is widespread in language, and not restricted to knowledge attributions, so it should not be considered problematic. I will argue that Montminy might be right about this, but that contextualists still face a serious and related problem: that it is a consequence of epistemic contextualism that subjects are typically unaware of contents conveyed by knowledge attributions, independently of whether these are semantic or non-semantic contents. Even if semantic blindness is widespread in language, it does not seem that content unawareness of this sort is. 相似文献