全文获取类型
收费全文 | 390篇 |
免费 | 3篇 |
国内免费 | 3篇 |
专业分类
396篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 2篇 |
2024年 | 8篇 |
2023年 | 13篇 |
2022年 | 5篇 |
2021年 | 8篇 |
2020年 | 23篇 |
2019年 | 30篇 |
2018年 | 23篇 |
2017年 | 29篇 |
2016年 | 27篇 |
2015年 | 24篇 |
2014年 | 20篇 |
2013年 | 44篇 |
2012年 | 20篇 |
2011年 | 4篇 |
2010年 | 6篇 |
2009年 | 13篇 |
2008年 | 4篇 |
2007年 | 5篇 |
2006年 | 9篇 |
2005年 | 9篇 |
2004年 | 5篇 |
2003年 | 19篇 |
2002年 | 13篇 |
2001年 | 6篇 |
2000年 | 3篇 |
1999年 | 8篇 |
1998年 | 2篇 |
1997年 | 3篇 |
1996年 | 1篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 2篇 |
1992年 | 1篇 |
1991年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 3篇 |
排序方式: 共有396条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
191.
When people engage in a task, they often take preliminary actions (preprocessing) to simplify primary processing. Usually, a trade‐off is made between the costs of preprocessing and primary processing. We conducted three experiments to find out whether people could adaptively estimate the utility of preprocessing depending on the task situation. The result demonstrated that in performing a high‐complexity task, almost all the participants reduced their overall task performance cost by conducting cost‐adaptive preprocessing. However, for a low‐complexity task, participants tended to conduct preprocessing even though this increased overall task performance cost. Based on these results, we discuss human nature from the viewpoint of the influence of cognitive effort. 相似文献
192.
Michael Huemer 《Metaphilosophy》2005,36(4):522-531
Abstract: There are at least three strategies we might take in approaching controversial issues: (i) we might accept the conclusions of experts on their authority, (ii) we might evaluate the relevant evidence and arguments for ourselves, or (iii) we might give up on finding the answers. Students of “critical thinking” are regularly advised to follow strategy (ii). But strategies (i) and (iii) are usually superior to (ii), from the standpoint of the goal of gaining true beliefs and avoiding false ones. 相似文献
193.
Brian Ribeiro 《Metaphilosophy》2004,35(5):714-732
Abstract: Recent literature on skepticism has raised a nearly univocal voice in condemning skeptical argumentation on the grounds that such argumentation necessarily involves our adopting some nonordinary or unnatural perspective. Were this really so, then skeptical conclusions would not speak to us in the way in which skeptics think they do; we would be “insulated” from any such conclusions. I argue that skeptical argumentation need not rely on any nonordinary or unnatural standards. Rather, the skeptic's procedure is to offer a critique from within. Having given my argument for this claim (which I call the Continuity Argument), I consider and respond to two important objections. I conclude that the skeptic has a powerful meta‐argument to be deployed in defending the legitimacy of his skeptical conclusions against the slings and arrows of (those I call) the half‐true theorists. 相似文献
194.
Thomas Schmidt 《Philosophical explorations》2016,19(1):17-27
Instrumentalism is the view that all requirements of practical reason can be derived from the instrumental principle, that is, from the claim that one ought to take the suitable means to one's ends. Rationalists, by contrast, hold that there are requirements of practical reason that concern the normative acceptability of ends. To the extent that rationalists put forward these requirements in addition to the instrumental principle, rationalism might seem to go beyond instrumentalism in its normative commitments. This is why it is sometimes thought that rationalism is stronger than instrumentalism in a way that entails that instrumentalism is the default view, while rationalists carry the burden of proof. In this paper, I explore and discuss different ways of spelling out this idea. I argue that rationalism is not stronger than instrumentalism in a way that has implications for matters of justification and differences in prima facie defensibility of the two sorts of views. 相似文献
195.
Ariel Zylberman 《Canadian journal of philosophy》2016,46(3):291-317
What is the relationship between human rights and the rights of states? Roughly, while cosmopolitans insist that international morality must regard as basic the interests of individuals, statists maintain that the state is of fundamental moral significance. This article defends a relational version of statism. Human rights are ultimately grounded in a relational norm of reciprocal independence and set limits to the exercise of public authority, but, contra the cosmopolitan, the state is of fundamental moral significance. A relational account promises to justify a limited conception of state sovereignty while avoiding the familiar cosmopolitan criticisms of statist accounts. 相似文献
196.
Theodore Kisiel 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2013,21(2):185-208
Abstract 1 This paper makes a preliminary case for a central and radical claim. I begin with Bernard Williams’ seldom-faced argument that integrity cannot be a moral virtue because it lacks two key ingredients of moral virtues, namely a characteristic thought and motivation. Whereas, for example, generosity involves the thought that another could use assistance, and the motivation to actually give assistance, integrity lacks these two things essential to morally excellent responses. I show that several maneuvers aimed at avoiding Williams’ challenge fail and that others are likely to remain unpersuasive. The paper concludes by offering an argument to the best explanation: Williams’ important insight is best explained by the supposition that integrity is an epistemic virtue, and an epistemic virtue of a practical sort. 相似文献
197.
《心理学报》2025,57(6)
人类通过外包部分认知任务给外部生成式人工智能技术来提升任务完成的效率和质量, 但认知外包的效果因人而异。为了揭示有效认知外包的关键特征和内在要求, 研究设计了一个面向研究生的认知外包活动, 参与者在生成式人工智能系统的协助下撰写开放性主题文章, 并依据文章得分被划分为高绩效组和低绩效组。通过对知识前测的差异性分析发现高绩效组的先前领域知识水平显著高于低绩效组。通过对交互过程数据进行滞后序列分析和认知网络分析, 发现两组群体在交互行为模式和认知结构特征上存在差异: 高绩效组的行为转换更加多元, 形成“快速自主的任务理解与规划——高效精准的人机互动——选择性提取与深度加工”的行为模式; 高绩效组的认知结构较为均衡和完整, 表现为交互中各认知元素间相对多样且紧密的关联, 而低绩效组的认知结构相对失衡和松散, 表现为对低层次认知元素的偏向和各元素间相对单一且微弱的关联。综合来看, 有效认知外包是个体在认知活动中积极参与、深入加工的复杂过程, 需要内外部认知网络的平衡与有效连接的建立。 相似文献
198.
Hsueh Qu 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2017,95(4):644-657
This paper will argue that Hume's notion of the self in Book 2 of the Treatise seems subject to two constraints. First, it should be a succession of perceptions [THN 2.2.1.2, 2.1.2.3]. Second, it should be durable in virtue of the roles that it plays with regard to pride and humility, as well as to normativity. However, I argue that these two constraints are in tension, since our perceptions are too transient to play these roles. I argue that this notion of self should be characterized as a bundle of dispositions to our perceptions, such that these dispositions are durable and counterfactual-supporting. I argue that Hume confused his ‘philosophical’ notion of dispositions, as nothing above and beyond their effects, with the thicker notion of dispositions to which the passions respond—which explains his mistaken commitment to the durability constraint. 相似文献
199.
Juli Eflin 《Metaphilosophy》2003,34(1&2):48-68
Traditional epistemology has, in the main, presupposed that the primary task is to give a complete account of the concept knowledge and to state under what conditions it is possible to have it. In so doing, most accounts have been hierarchical, and all assume an idealized knower. The assumption of an idealized knower is essential for the traditional goal of generating an unassailable account of knowledge acquisition. Yet we, as individuals, fail to reach the ideal. Perhaps more important, we have epistemic goals not addressed in the traditional approach – among them, the ability to reach understanding in areas we deem important for our lives. Understanding is an epistemic concept. But how we obtain it has not traditionally been a focus. Developing an epistemic account that starts from a set of assumptions that differ from the traditional starting points will allow a different sort of epistemic theory, one on which generating understanding is a central goal and the idealized knower is replaced with an inquirer who is not merely fallible but working from a particular context with particular goals. Insight into how an epistemic account can include the particular concerns of an embedded inquirer can be found by examining the parallels between ethics and epistemology and, in particular, by examining the structure and starting points of virtue accounts. Here I develop several interrelated issues that contrast the goals and evaluative concepts that form the structure of both standard, traditional epistemological and ethical theories and virtue–centered theories. In the end, I sketch a virtue–centered epistemology that accords with who we are and how we gain understanding. 相似文献
200.
Suppose we have a stack of cards that is divided over some players. For certain distributions of cards it is possible to communicate your hand of cards to another player by public announcements, without yet another player learning any of your cards. A solution to this problem consists of some sequence of announcements and is called an exchange. It is called a direct exchange if it consists of (the minimum of) two announcements only. The announcements in an exchange have a special form: they are safe communications, an interesting new form of update. Certain unsafe communications turn out to be unsuccessful updates. A communication is a public announcement that is known to be true. Each communication may be about a set of alternative card deals only, and even about a set of alternatives to the communicating player's own hand only. We list the direct exchanges for a deal of seven cards where the two players holding three cards communicate their hands to each other. Our work may be applicable to the design of cryptographic protocols. 相似文献