全文获取类型
收费全文 | 307篇 |
免费 | 9篇 |
国内免费 | 3篇 |
专业分类
319篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 4篇 |
2023年 | 7篇 |
2022年 | 3篇 |
2021年 | 9篇 |
2020年 | 21篇 |
2019年 | 32篇 |
2018年 | 15篇 |
2017年 | 13篇 |
2016年 | 6篇 |
2015年 | 10篇 |
2014年 | 9篇 |
2013年 | 34篇 |
2012年 | 7篇 |
2011年 | 8篇 |
2010年 | 5篇 |
2009年 | 5篇 |
2008年 | 14篇 |
2007年 | 12篇 |
2006年 | 9篇 |
2005年 | 10篇 |
2004年 | 12篇 |
2003年 | 8篇 |
2002年 | 10篇 |
2001年 | 7篇 |
2000年 | 7篇 |
1999年 | 7篇 |
1998年 | 7篇 |
1997年 | 5篇 |
1996年 | 2篇 |
1994年 | 5篇 |
1992年 | 3篇 |
1991年 | 2篇 |
1990年 | 2篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 6篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有319条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
181.
Mats Bergman 《Studies in Philosophy and Education》2005,24(3-4):213-233
This article examines the contention that the central concepts of C. S. Peirce’s semeiotic are inherently communicational. It is argued that the Peircean approach avoids the pitfalls of objectivism and constructivism, rendering the sign-user neither a passive recipient nor an omnipotent creator of meaning. Consequently, semeiotic may serve as a useful general framework for studies of learning processes. 相似文献
182.
Transzendentalpragmatik und Diskursethik. Elemente und Perspektiven der Apelschen Diskursphilosophie
Dietrich Böhler 《Journal for General Philosophy of Science》2003,34(2):221-249
Transcendental Pragmatics and Discourse Ethics. Elements and Perspectives of Apel's Discourse-Philosophy. The author follows Apel's intellectual biography and shows the conception of a critique of meaning qua ‘reflection upon the discourse within the discourse’ to be the centre of Apel's language-pragmatic ‘Transformation of Philosophy’ (Frankfurt a.M. 1973). Beginning
with an explication of the situation of a speaker/thinker, especially of the situation of a philosophising speaker/thinker,
Apel reconstructs a two fold apriori of communication: Every thought is situated within the context of a particular, historically
evolved, community of language and interaction. At the same time, however, the validity-claims of thoughts transcend the context
of their origin towards an unlimited community of argumentation. On the basis of the first apriori Apel criticises the methodical
solipsism as well as the objectivism of modern philosophy and theory of science. Drawing upon the second apriori he develops
a universalist critique of meaning of relativism and contextualism. In the sixties and seventies Apel worked out a differentiated
theory of the – more or less – communicatively cognizing humanities and set it apart from the theory of the causal-explanatory
natural sciences, thus challenging the objectivism of a Theory of Unified Science. Building upon this work Transcendental
Pragmatics, as developed by Apel and others, sets philosophy primarily two tasks: firstly, a (fallible) internal reconstruction of argumentative discourse as the (logical) situation of speech and thought which seeks to elucidate the conditions of the
meaningfulness, i. e. the presuppositions, of discourse. These presuppositions comprise, thus Apel with Habermas, the four
validity-claims to intelligibility, sincerety/credibility, truth and normative rightness/legitimacy. Their moral content consists,
thus Apel, not only in the recognition of the equality of all beings capable of discursive reasoning but also in their recognition
of a co-responsibility for the realizability of discourses and of responsibility. The author argues that the existence of
a co-responsibility of this kind is indisputable because the discursive claims to validity are intertwined with a set of ‘primordial
promises of dialogue’. Only with the elucidation and explication of these promises can the reconstruction of the internal
conditions of discourse be completed.The second task of a pragmatics of argumentation isthe strict resp. actual reflection of the thinker upon the presuppositions of the discourse in which he currently engages. This reflection has a Socratic character
and can only be done in the form of discussion and debate (‘Auseinandersetzungen’, Apel, Frankfurt a.M. 1998) with critics
of the reconstruction. In this context, the author proposes a method of Socratic reflection upon the presuppositions of dialogue
which suspends the usual, theoretically oriented, attitude of the scientist and the philosopher in favour of an actual reflective attitude. Within a dialogue with a sceptic who doubts one of the results of the internal reconstruction of dialogical presuppositions,
say X, it is tested whether his doubt as to the unrestricted validity of X can be understood as a sincere contribution to
the current dialogue or whether this particular sceptical thesis does not make sense, because it is incompatible with the
role of a sincere participant of argumentation which, after all, the sceptic cannot refuse to claim for himself.Finally the
author explains Apel's characterization of the tension between “Discourse and Responsibility” (Frankfurt a.M. 1988). In the
course of discussions with Max Weber, Lawrence Kohlberg, Hans Jonas et al., Apel formulates and justifies an ethics of responsibility and gives an affirmative answer to the crucial question of whether
the fulfilment of the moral obligations connected with the recognition of co-responsibility can be demanded within the non-dialogical
circumstances of social reality. Apel's answer employs the idea of counter-strategies which are morally legitimate in virtue
of their being worthy of argumentative consensus.
This revised version was published online in August 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
183.
184.
Abstract. A dialogue between the outgoing and incoming directors of the Zygon Center for Religion and Science took place as part of the inaugural symposium. In their conversation they speak of the past and present challenges and goals of the Center, outline what is foremost in their minds, and offer glimpses into what they see as the Center's priorities for future work. 相似文献
185.
《Metaphilosophy》1999,30(1&2):95-123
Books reviewed:
Raymond D. Boisvert, John Dewey: Rethinking Our Time
Larry A. Hickman, ed., Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a Postmodern Generation
Jennifer Welchman, Dewey's Ethical Thought
Richard Shusterman, Practicing Philosophy: Pragmatism and the Philosophical Life
Richard E. Hart and Douglas R. Anderson, eds., Philosophy in Experience: American Philosophy in Transition
Richard Kearney, Poetics of Modernity: Toward a Hermeneutic Imagination 相似文献
Raymond D. Boisvert, John Dewey: Rethinking Our Time
Larry A. Hickman, ed., Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a Postmodern Generation
Jennifer Welchman, Dewey's Ethical Thought
Richard Shusterman, Practicing Philosophy: Pragmatism and the Philosophical Life
Richard E. Hart and Douglas R. Anderson, eds., Philosophy in Experience: American Philosophy in Transition
Richard Kearney, Poetics of Modernity: Toward a Hermeneutic Imagination 相似文献
186.
William E. Lesher 《Zygon》1999,34(2):255-263
This is a response from the point of view of religion to three articles—by Ewert Cousins, David Loye, and Solomon H. Katz—that together call for a decisive new moral grounding for the human race. This commentary calls on science, as the dominant power in society today, to initiate a new partnership with religion. It goes on to advocate for an urgent mutual-learning endeavor in which science and religion will derive needed information and understanding from each other. The commentary finds a common thread in the three articles—that religion informed by science is the principal force capable of stimulating a global moral transformation—and ends by proposing a series of concrete action steps. 相似文献
187.
In trying to control various aspects concerning utterance production in multi-party human–computer dialogue, argumentative
considerations play an important part, particularly in choosing appropriate lexical units so that we fine-tune the degree
of persuasion that each utterance has. A preliminary step in this endeavor is the ability to place an ordering relation between semantic
forms (that are due to be realized as utterances, by the machine), concerning their persuasion strength, with respect to certain
(explicit or implicit) conclusions. Thus, in this article, we propose a mechanism for assessing utterances, in terms of their
argumentative force. The framework designed conflates insights from Asher and Lascarides’ SDRT (“Segmented Discourse Representation Theory”),
and from Anscombre and Ducrot’s AT (“Argumentation Theory”). These mechanisms are included in a language generation component
of a multi-party dialogue system for book reservation applications (i.e., a “virtual librarian”), and thus evaluated via typical
human–machine conversations.
相似文献
Jean CaelenEmail: |
188.
Taeda Jovičić 《Argumentation》2006,20(1):29-58
In this article, I further analyze the notion of the effectiveness of argumentative strategies, introduced in Jovičić, 2001. The most relevant achievements of the theories of reasonable discussion and the theories of persuasion are called to mind with the aim of explaining the mechanism of the argumentative effectiveness. As a result, a procedure for evaluating the effectiveness of argumentative strategies is suggested. 相似文献
189.
《Islam & Christian-Muslim Relations》2012,23(3):329-345
The accumulation of exegetical discoveries (i.e., the similarity between the conciliar texts and his own position), testimonies, and respected opinions points to the probability that it is Louis Massignon's vision that dominates the Roman Catholic Church's statements regarding Islam in Lumen gentium and Nostra aetate. Although many commentators agree with that assessment, the concrete historical connections between Massignon and the conciliar pronouncements are not yet explained in sufficient detail. Building especially on the work of Robert Caspar, Maurice Borrmans, Michael Fitzgerald, Christian Troll, Anthony O'Mahony, and Andrew Unsworth, but other authors as well, this article begins to do just that, first by reading the Vatican II statements on Islam in the light of Massignon's work, and then by organizing the human connections between Massignon and the conciliar statements according to the degree of probability that said connections had real influence. 相似文献
190.
Millions of people leave their religion every year. Such defection often results in religious persecution, ostracism, and heightened intergroup conflict. Yet little is known about the underlying perceptions of religious defectors and what intergroup processes predict hostility toward them. In two pre-registered studies (N = 512), we investigated how religious group members' thoughts and feelings about defectors may lead to ostracism and a lack of dialogue. In both studies, group members rated defectors as unlikeable and irrational. Further, the strength of group members' religious group identification (but not religious belief conviction) predicted dislike and unwillingness to relate wisely with defectors (Study 2). Implications for intergroup research and improving the experience of religious defectors are discussed. 相似文献