全文获取类型
收费全文 | 2238篇 |
免费 | 176篇 |
国内免费 | 3篇 |
专业分类
2417篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 5篇 |
2024年 | 27篇 |
2023年 | 48篇 |
2022年 | 37篇 |
2021年 | 14篇 |
2020年 | 120篇 |
2019年 | 96篇 |
2018年 | 65篇 |
2017年 | 82篇 |
2016年 | 102篇 |
2015年 | 64篇 |
2014年 | 115篇 |
2013年 | 320篇 |
2012年 | 38篇 |
2011年 | 35篇 |
2010年 | 34篇 |
2009年 | 56篇 |
2008年 | 102篇 |
2007年 | 130篇 |
2006年 | 125篇 |
2005年 | 163篇 |
2004年 | 118篇 |
2003年 | 124篇 |
2002年 | 71篇 |
2001年 | 51篇 |
2000年 | 44篇 |
1999年 | 47篇 |
1998年 | 39篇 |
1997年 | 18篇 |
1996年 | 31篇 |
1995年 | 31篇 |
1994年 | 13篇 |
1993年 | 5篇 |
1992年 | 8篇 |
1991年 | 7篇 |
1990年 | 13篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 8篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
1981年 | 2篇 |
1978年 | 1篇 |
1977年 | 4篇 |
1975年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有2417条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
61.
George W. Harris 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》2002,5(3):271-286
The problem of pessimism is the secular analogue to the evidential problem of evil facing traditional theism. The traditional theist must argue two things: that the evidence shows that this is on balance a good world and that it is the best possible world. Though the secular optimist who advocates any form of secular moral theory need not argue that the current and future world will likely be the best possible world, she nonetheless must argue that were there a clean solution to the problem of current and future suffering in which all sentient life could be instantly and painlessly eliminated, we would have reasons not to employ the clean solution because the future promises to bring on balance a good world in which the evil of human and animal suffering is outweighed by whatever is good in the world. Pessimism is the view that the evidence argues against secular optimism. It is argued here that it is anything but clear that secular optimism is warranted when viewed from an impersonal point of view. The problem is then evaluated from the personal point of view in which a form of personal optimism is defended even in the face of impersonal pessimism. 相似文献
62.
Taylor PL 《Science and engineering ethics》2005,11(4):589-616
Key ethical issues arise in association with the conduct of stem cell research by research institutions in the United States.
These ethical issues, summarized in detail, receive no adequate translation into federal laws or regulations, also described
in this article. U.S. Federal policy takes a passive approach to these ethical issues, translating them simply into limitations
on taxpayer funding, and foregoes scientific and ethical leadership while protecting intellectual property interests through
a laissez faire approach to stem cell patents and licenses. Those patents and licenses, far from being scientifically and
ethically neutral in effect, virtually prohibit commercially sponsored research that could otherwise be a realistic alternative
to the federal funding gap. The lack of federal funding and related data-sharing principles, combined with the effect of U.S.
patent policy, the lack of key agency guidance, and the proliferation of divergent state laws arising from the lack of Federal
leadership, significantly impede ethical stem cell research in the United States, without coherently supporting any consensus
ethical vision. Research institutions must themselves implement steps, described in the article, to integrate addressing ethical
review with the many legal compliance issues U.S. federal and state laws create.
The opinions expressed in this article are the author’s own, and are not necessarily the opinions of others, including Children’s
Hospital Boston. Portions of earlier versions of this article were previously published by the American Bar Association and
the New York State Bar Association. 相似文献
63.
Nanotechnology — A new field of ethical inquiry? 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
Grunwald A 《Science and engineering ethics》2005,11(2):187-201
Parallel to the public discussion on the benefits and risks of nanotechnology, a debate on the ethics of nanotechnology has
begun. It has been postulated that a new “nano-ethics” is necessary. In this debate, the — positive as well as negative —
visionary and speculative innovations which are brought into connection with nanotechnology stand in the foreground. In this
contribution, an attempt is made to discover new ethical aspects of nanotechnology in a more systematic manner than has been
the case. It turns out that there are hardly any completely new ethical aspects raised by nanotechnology. It is much rather
primarily a case of gradual shifts of emphasis and of relevance in questions which, in principle, are already known and which
give reason for ethical discussions on nanotechnology. In a certain manner, structurally novel ethical aspects arise through
the important role played by visions in the public discourse. New questions are also posed by the fact that previously separate
lines of ethical reflection converge in the field of nanotechnology. The proposal of an independent “nano-ethics”, however,
seems exaggerated. 相似文献
64.
65.
The present essay offers a sketch of a philosophy of value, what I shall here refer to as ‘ethical instrumentalism.’ My primary
aim is to say just what this view involves and what its commitments are. In the course of doing so, I find it necessary to
distinguish this view from another with which it shares a common basis and which, in reference to its most influential proponent,
I refer to as ‘Humeanism.’ A second, more general, aim is to make plausible the idea that, given the common basis, ethical
instrumentalism provides a more compelling picture of the philosophy of value than Humeanism does. 相似文献
66.
Emison GA 《Science and engineering ethics》2004,10(2):225-233
The ethical choices faced by engineers today are increasingly complex. Competing and conflicting ethical demands from clients,
communities, employees, and personal objectives combine to suggest that engineers employ ethical approaches that are adaptive
yet grounded in three concrete professional circumstances: first, that engineers apply unique professional skills in the service
of a client, subject to protecting the public interest; second, that engineers advance the state of knowledge of their professional
field through reflection, research, and sharing experience in journals and conferences, and third, that they develop new professionals
by active mentoring. This paper examines five features of American pragmatism and suggests that its emphasis on specific,
context-based ethical decision making can assist engineers in a postmodern setting. In particular, it considers the venues
of interpersonal ethical choices, institutional ethical conflicts, and social choices that have ethical components. Pragmatism
suggests that in such a complex ethical climate, there is a need for the co-evolution of judgment and action, for individual
reflective judgment in particular situations, and for ceasing to search for a single, immutable principle for ethical choice.
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the “Ethics and Social Responsibility in Engineering and Technology” meeting,
New Orleans, 2003. 相似文献
67.
McGinn RE 《Science and engineering ethics》2003,9(4):517-542
A survey on ethical issues in engineering was administered over a five-year period to Stanford engineering students and practicing
engineers. Analysis of its results strongly suggests that important disconnects exist between the education of engineering
students regarding ethical issues in engineering on the one hand, and the realities of contemporary engineering practice on
the other. Two noteworthy consequences of these gaps are that the views of engineering students differ substantially over
what makes an issue an ethical issue, while practicing engineers exhibit significant disagreement over what is the most important
non-technical aspect of being a responsible engineering professional in contemporary society. These divergences impede the
recognition of ethical issues and of specific moral responsibilities of engineers in concrete professional practice. It is
argued that the use of suitably refined and probing surveys of engineering students and practicing engineers about ethical
issues in engineering is an important although neglected empirical approach to the study of engineering ethics. Such an approach
can enhance the prevailing case study method and combat over-tidy theoretical-analytical approaches to the subject.
When a train arrives at a station in the London Underground, a public announcement cautions passengers to “mind the gap”,
i.e. heed the space between the station platform and the carriage while entering or exiting.
An early draft of this paper was presented at the International Conference on Ethics in Engineering and Computer Science,
Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, Ohio, March 21–23, 1999. 相似文献
68.
This article focuses mainly on (1) the policy of Delft University of Technology since 1992 as regards the university-wide
introduction of a compulsory course on ethics and engineering, and (2) the ideal structure of such a course, including the
educational goals of the course.
Dr. G. J. Scheurwater is Senior policy-advisor to the Board of Delft University of Technology.
Prof. S. J. Doorman is Chairman of the Advisory Committee on Ethics of Delft University of Technology. 相似文献
69.
This article reports on the development and teaching of compulsory courses on ethics and engineering at Delft University of
Technology (DUT). Attention is paid to the teaching goals, the educational setup and methods, the contents of the courses,
involvement of staff from engineering schools, experiences to date, and challenges for the future. The choices made with respect
to the development and teaching of the courses are placed within the European and Dutch context and are compared and contrasted
with the American situation and experiences.
Previous versions of this article were presented at the meeting of the SEFI Working Group on Engineering Ethics in Rzeszow,
Poland, April 29–May 1, 1999 and at the SEFI Annual Conference in Zurich, Switzerland, September 1–3, 1999. 相似文献
70.
In this editorial contribution, two issues relevant to the question, what should be at the top of the research agenda for ethics and technology, are identified and discussed. Firstly: can, and do, engineers make a difference to the degree to which technology leads to morally desirable outcomes? What role does professional autonomy play here, and what are its limits? And secondly, what should be the scope of engineers' responsibility; that is to say, on which issues are they, as engineers, morally obliged to reflect? The research agendas proposed by the authors contributing to this special section, implicitly, give different answers to these questions. We suggest that an explicit discussion of these issues would greatly help in constructing a common research agenda. 相似文献