全文获取类型
收费全文 | 241篇 |
免费 | 24篇 |
国内免费 | 2篇 |
专业分类
267篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 3篇 |
2023年 | 3篇 |
2022年 | 1篇 |
2021年 | 3篇 |
2020年 | 11篇 |
2019年 | 6篇 |
2018年 | 15篇 |
2017年 | 9篇 |
2016年 | 13篇 |
2015年 | 4篇 |
2014年 | 10篇 |
2013年 | 24篇 |
2012年 | 9篇 |
2011年 | 15篇 |
2010年 | 8篇 |
2009年 | 16篇 |
2008年 | 17篇 |
2007年 | 18篇 |
2006年 | 12篇 |
2005年 | 7篇 |
2004年 | 15篇 |
2003年 | 9篇 |
2002年 | 12篇 |
2001年 | 2篇 |
2000年 | 3篇 |
1999年 | 4篇 |
1998年 | 4篇 |
1997年 | 1篇 |
1996年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 3篇 |
1993年 | 1篇 |
1988年 | 1篇 |
1981年 | 1篇 |
1978年 | 3篇 |
1977年 | 1篇 |
1976年 | 2篇 |
排序方式: 共有267条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
91.
We formalise a notion of dynamic rationality in terms of a logic of conditional beliefs on (doxastic) plausibility models.
Similarly to other epistemic statements (e.g. negations of Moore sentences and of Muddy Children announcements), dynamic rationality
changes its meaning after every act of learning, and it may become true after players learn it is false. Applying this to
extensive games, we “simulate” the play of a game as a succession of dynamic updates of the original plausibility model: the
epistemic situation when a given node is reached can be thought of as the result of a joint act of learning (via public announcements)
that the node is reached. We then use the notion of “stable belief”, i.e. belief that is preserved during the play of the
game, in order to give an epistemic condition for backward induction: rationality and common knowledge of stable belief in
rationality. This condition is weaker than Aumann’s and compatible with the implicit assumptions (the “epistemic openness
of the future”) underlying Stalnaker’s criticism of Aumann’s proof. The “dynamic” nature of our concept of rationality explains
why our condition avoids the apparent circularity of the “backward induction paradox”: it is consistent to (continue to) believe
in a player’s rationality after updating with his irrationality. 相似文献
92.
We present a framework that provides a logic for science by generalizing the notion of logical (Tarskian) consequence. This framework will introduce hierarchies of logical consequences, the first level of each of which is identified with deduction. We argue for identification of the second level of the hierarchies with inductive inference. The notion of induction presented here has some resonance with Popper's notion of scientific discovery by refutation. Our framework rests on the assumption of a restricted class of structures in contrast to the permissibility of classical first-order logic. We make a distinction between deductive and inductive inference via the notions of compactness and weak compactness. Connections with the arithmetical hierarchy and formal learning theory are explored. For the latter, we argue against the identification of inductive inference with the notion of learnable in the limit. Several results highlighting desirable properties of these hierarchies of generalized logical consequence are also presented. 相似文献
93.
We consider the desirability, or otherwise, of various forms of induction in the light of certain principles and inductive methods within predicate uncertain reasoning. Our general conclusion is that there remain conflicts within the area whose resolution will require a deeper understanding of the fundamental relationship between individuals and properties. 相似文献
94.
Kevin Wallbridge 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2018,96(1):118-126
Sosa, Pritchard, and Vogel have all argued that there are cases in which one knows something inductively but does not believe it sensitively, and that sensitivity therefore cannot be necessary for knowledge. I defend sensitivity by showing that inductive knowledge is sensitive. 相似文献
95.
Ute Habel Egbert Kühn Jasmin B. Salloum Helmut Devos Frank Schneider 《Aggressive behavior》2002,28(5):394-400
Emotional‐processing deficits may be one of the characteristic features of impaired affect in individuals with psychopathy. These include shallowness and profound lack of remorse or empathy. Performances on standardized emotion discrimination tasks and mood induction tasks were compared between 17 patients with antisocial personality disorder (DSM‐IV) and 17 nonpsychopaths. Subjects with psychopathic personality demonstrated poorer performance on emotion‐discrimination tasks compared with controls. However, higher scores on factor “emotional detachment” of the Psychopathy Checklist (PCL‐R) were associated with better discrimination ability. Subjective ratings were comparable between groups during mood induction. Although the findings support the hypothesis of a significant association between impaired emotional processing and psychopathy, they also suggest a relationship between emotional discrimination and the core personality features of psychopathy. Aggr. Behav. 28:394–400, 2002. © 2002 Wiley‐Liss, Inc. 相似文献
96.
97.
98.
促排卵药物在临床中的广泛应用,给不孕患者带来了希望,另一方面促排卵带来的风险也越来越引起人们的重视,如卵巢过度刺激综合征(OHSS)、妊娠并发症、出生缺陷和肿瘤等。因此,用哲学的观点客观地看待促排卵的成效与风险之间的关系有助于临床医生进一步提高促排卵安全性的认识,做出正确的决策。 相似文献
99.
分子遗传学中心法则提示,遗传信息由蛋白质向DNA的输入过程在蛋白质和RNA之间是断开的。而获得性特异性免疫反应的产生却意味着机体遇到外来抗原入侵后存在信息增加的过程。本文由此假设:1存在立体结构特异性逆翻译酶,介导信息由蛋白质向RNA的传递;2特异性免疫应答形成过程中,逆翻译酶按外来抗原的空间结构合成针对外来抗原的基因片段,是免疫特异性形成的核心 相似文献
100.
This article proposes a new model of human concept learning that provides a rational analysis of learning feature-based concepts. This model is built upon Bayesian inference for a grammatically structured hypothesis space—a concept language of logical rules. This article compares the model predictions to human generalization judgments in several well-known category learning experiments, and finds good agreement for both average and individual participant generalizations. This article further investigates judgments for a broad set of 7-feature concepts—a more natural setting in several ways—and again finds that the model explains human performance. 相似文献