全文获取类型
收费全文 | 581篇 |
免费 | 14篇 |
专业分类
595篇 |
出版年
2023年 | 5篇 |
2022年 | 2篇 |
2021年 | 11篇 |
2020年 | 6篇 |
2019年 | 19篇 |
2018年 | 18篇 |
2017年 | 25篇 |
2016年 | 12篇 |
2015年 | 16篇 |
2014年 | 14篇 |
2013年 | 54篇 |
2012年 | 10篇 |
2011年 | 8篇 |
2010年 | 11篇 |
2009年 | 19篇 |
2008年 | 21篇 |
2007年 | 24篇 |
2006年 | 16篇 |
2005年 | 29篇 |
2004年 | 9篇 |
2003年 | 14篇 |
2002年 | 9篇 |
2001年 | 5篇 |
2000年 | 5篇 |
1999年 | 2篇 |
1998年 | 3篇 |
1997年 | 3篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 1篇 |
1987年 | 5篇 |
1985年 | 13篇 |
1984年 | 16篇 |
1983年 | 19篇 |
1982年 | 23篇 |
1981年 | 12篇 |
1980年 | 21篇 |
1979年 | 20篇 |
1978年 | 29篇 |
1977年 | 15篇 |
1976年 | 19篇 |
1975年 | 6篇 |
1974年 | 15篇 |
1973年 | 10篇 |
排序方式: 共有595条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
521.
Louise Cummings 《Argumentation》2004,18(1):61-94
In this paper, I examine the incessant call to theory that is evident in fallacy inquiry. I relate the motivations for this call to a desire to attain for fallacy inquiry certain attributes of the theoretical process in scientific inquiry. I argue that these same attributes, when pursued in the context of philosophical inquiry in general and fallacy inquiry in particular, lead to the assumption of a metaphysical standpoint. This standpoint, I contend, is generative of unintelligibility in philosophical discussions of rationality. I claim that this same unintelligibility can be shown to characterise fallacy inquiry, an example of the study of argumentative rationality. The context for my claim is an examination of the theoretical pronouncements of two prominent fallacy theorists, John Woods and Douglas Walton, in relation to the argument from ignorance fallacy. My conclusion takes the form of guidelines for the post-theoretical pursuit of fallacy inquiry. 相似文献
522.
523.
524.
525.
526.
Julian Dodd 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2018,96(4):629-641
What is John Cage's 4′33″? This paper disambiguates this question into three sub-questions concerning, respectively, the work's ontological nature, the art form to which it belongs, and the genre it is in. We shall see that the work's performances consist of silence (rather than containing environmental sounds), that it is a work of performance art (rather than music), and that it belongs to the genre of conceptual art. Seeing the work in these ways helps us to understand it better, and promises to assuage somewhat the puzzlement and irritation of those who are at first resistant to its charms. 相似文献
527.
Drawing chiefly on recent sources, in Part One I sketch an untraditional way of articulating what I claim to be central elements of traditional Catholic morality, treating it as based in virtues, focused on the recipients ("patients") of our attention and concern, and centered in certain person-to-person role-relationships. I show the limited and derivative places of "natural law," and therefore of sin, within that framework. I also sketch out some possible implications for medical ethics of this approach to moral theory, and briefly contrast these with the influential alternative offered by the "principlism" of Beauchamp and Childress. In Part Two, I turn to a Catholic understanding of the nature and meaning of human suffering, drawing especially on writings and addresses of the late Pope John Paul II. He reminds us that physical and mental suffering can provide an opportunity to share in Christ's salvific sacrifice, better to see the nature of our earthly vocation, and to reflect on the dependence that inheres in human existence. At various places, and especially in my conclusion, I suggest a few ways in which this can inform bioethical reflection on morally appropriate responses to those afflicted by physical or mental pain, disability, mental impairment, disease, illness, and poor health prospects. My general point is that mercy must be informed by appreciation of the person's dignity and status. Throughout, my approach is philosophical rather than theological. 相似文献
528.
529.
Pliskoff SS 《Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior》1977,28(2):185-187
The history of the stellar magnitude scale is briefly traced from the second century b.c. until the middle of the nineteenth century. It becomes clear that astronomers formulated "Fechner's Law" by about 1850. While Fechner is credited with the grander view of things, the contention is made that the astronomers John Herschel, W. R. Dawes, and N. R. Pogson have not been given their due by historians of psychology. 相似文献
530.
Edna B. Foa Gail Steketee Ralph M. Turner Steven C. Fischer 《Behaviour research and therapy》1980,18(5):449-455
The combined effects of imaginal exposure to feared catastrophes and in vivo exposure to external stimuli were compared with the effects of in vivo exposure alone in 15 obsessive-compulsives with checking rituals. The first group received 90 min of uninterrupted exposure in imagination, which concentrated mainly on disastrous consequences, followed by 30 min of exposure in vivo to stimuli-situations which triggered rituals. The second group was given 2 hr of exposure in vivo only. Both groups were prevented from performing rituals. Treatment consisted of 10 daily sessions within a 2 week period.Assessments were conducted before and after treatment and at follow-up ranging from 3 months to 2.5 yr with a mean of 11 months. At post-treatment both groups improved considerably and did not differ. But at follow-up those who received imaginal and in vivo exposure maintained their gains, whereas the group who were treated by exposure in vivo alone evidenced partial relapse on four of the six dependent measures. The results tend to indicate that a closer match between a patient's internal fear model and the content of exposure enhances long term treatment efficacy. 相似文献