全文获取类型
收费全文 | 287篇 |
免费 | 10篇 |
专业分类
297篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 4篇 |
2023年 | 9篇 |
2021年 | 5篇 |
2020年 | 10篇 |
2019年 | 8篇 |
2018年 | 9篇 |
2017年 | 20篇 |
2016年 | 17篇 |
2015年 | 5篇 |
2014年 | 12篇 |
2013年 | 28篇 |
2012年 | 11篇 |
2011年 | 5篇 |
2010年 | 7篇 |
2009年 | 16篇 |
2008年 | 23篇 |
2007年 | 18篇 |
2006年 | 24篇 |
2005年 | 18篇 |
2004年 | 11篇 |
2003年 | 8篇 |
2002年 | 11篇 |
2001年 | 3篇 |
2000年 | 1篇 |
1999年 | 2篇 |
1998年 | 2篇 |
1997年 | 1篇 |
1996年 | 5篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1992年 | 1篇 |
1991年 | 1篇 |
1988年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有297条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
191.
Structures and Structural Realism 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
192.
Anne Sophie Meincke 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2019,27(1):12-30
This paper aims to motivate a new beginning in metaphysical thinking about persistence by drawing attention to the disappearance of change in current accounts of persistence. I defend the claim that the debate is stuck in a dilemma which results from neglecting the constructive role of change for persistence. Neither of the two main competing views, perdurantism and endurantism, captures the idea of persistence as an identity through time. I identify the fundamental ontological reasons for this, namely the shared commitment to what I call ‘thing ontology’: an ontology that gives the ontological priority to static things. I conclude by briefly indicating how switching to a process ontological framework that takes process and change to be ontologically primary may allow for overcoming the dilemma of persistence. 相似文献
193.
Pablo R. Velasco 《Metaphilosophy》2017,48(5):712-726
This paper investigates ontological dimensions of the blockchain by asking what kind of socio‐technical object bitcoin is. It discusses both blockchain's political qualities and the political forms enabled by its emergence. It first observes recent approaches to the ontology of money and the political qualities of the ledgers used by the current fractional reserve banking model. It then directs the same questions at blockchain technology. The paper discusses an ontology proposed by Ole Bjerg ( 2016 ) and argues in favour of a mixed‐ontology approach to blockchains. It then questions the political qualities of the distributed ledger as a digital object and highlights the apparent absence of authority figures in the model. Finally, it argues that the political ontology of the blockchain can be framed as the displacement of authority from institutional actors into instrumental control of trust, in a dynamically distributed environment. 相似文献
194.
David Suarez 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2017,25(4):437-453
Naturalists seek to ground what exists in a set of fundamental metaphysical principles that they call ‘nature’. But metaphysical principles can’t function as fundamental explanatory grounds, since their ability to explain anything depends on the intelligibility granted by transcendental structures. What makes metaphysical principles intelligible, what unifies them, and allows them to characterize the being of worldly objects are the transcendental structures through which worldly objects are manifest. This means that the search for fundamental explanatory grounds must go deeper than the postulation of brute metaphysical facts. But this search cannot end with transcendental structures either, since the mode of being of transcendental subjects also calls out for explanation. Conceiving of transcendental subjects through the concept of being-in-the-world ties the mode of being of subjects to the world they inhabit. What grounds the existence of worldly objects, and what grounds our existence as being-in-the-world is nature: a principle that is neither an object, nor a subject – a principle that makes possible our encounters with intelligible worldly things. 相似文献
195.
Dimitris Apostolopoulos 《British Journal for the History of Philosophy》2018,26(2):348-370
This paper attempts to clarify Merleau-Ponty’s later work by tracing a hitherto overlooked set of concerns that were of key consequence for the formulation of his ontological research. I argue that his ontology can be understood as a response to a set of problems originating in reflections on the intersubjective use of language in dialogue, undertaken in the early 1950s. His study of dialogue disclosed a structure of meaning-formation and pointed towards a theory of truth (both recurring ontological topics) that post-Phenomenology premises could not account for. A study of dialogue shows that speakers’ positions are interchangeable, that speaking subjects are active and passive in varying degrees, and that the intentional roles of subjects and objects are liable to shift or ‘transgress’ themselves. These observations anticipate the concepts of ‘reversibility’ and ‘narcissism’, his later view of activity and passivity, and his later view of intentionality, and sharpened the need to adopt an intersubjective focus in ontological research. 相似文献
196.
Sean Petranovich 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2018,26(2):251-274
AbstractThis paper provides an interpretation of trust and betrayal within political communities from the perspective of Husserl’s concept of social communities. I situate the paper amidst Margaret Gilbert’s theory of political obligations, arguing that at least one outside conception of trust fills a gap left in her theory. More specifically, I argue for the supplementary fit that Karen Jones’s conception of trust understood as ‘basal security’ provides for Gilbert. From there, I tie this conception of trust and betrayal to Husserl’s notions of ‘original belief’ and socio-cultural crisis. There is thereby a phenomenological elucidation of features within the social world that allow such crises to occur in the first place. 相似文献
197.
Willem B. Drees 《Zygon》1998,33(4):617-633
Religious naturalism refers here to a view of reality, and it will be contrasted with versions of supernaturalism and of atheistic naturalism. Naturalistic religion refers to certain varieties of religion, especially some inspired by the universality of science and the need for a global ethics. In this essay I explicate why a religious naturalist need not advocate a naturalistic religion. Rather, a religious naturalist can build upon the heritage of religious traditions and be open to, but at the same time be agnostic about, the idea of a nonnatural ground of reality . The religious naturalism I defend has been criticized from various directions: one reviewer in this journal considered it too much indebted to the traditions, and hence "reactionary" and supernaturalistic; another considered it too minimalist in its religion ("virtually nonexistent") as a consequence of the preference for a too sober version of naturalism. My distinction between religious naturalism and naturalistic religion may answer some of these objections. 相似文献
198.
Katherine Ritchie 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2016,94(1):24-41
Since the linguistic turn, many have taken semantics to guide ontology. Here, I argue that semantics can, at best, serve as a partial guide to ontological commitment. If semantics were to be our guide, semantic data and semantic treatments would need to be taken seriously. Through an examination of plurals and their treatments, I argue that there can be multiple, equally semantically adequate, treatments of a natural language theory. Further, such treatments can attribute different ontological commitments to a theory. Given this, I argue that semantics can fail to deliver determinate ontological commitments and determinate answers to ontological questions, more generally. 相似文献
199.
Gad Yair 《Social Psychology of Education》1996,1(3):269-295
This study presents an exploratory theoretical framework that analyzes the extent by which the contexts of classroom instruction
mediate the effects of instructional strategies on achievement. The study first presents the two main tasks that teachers
face in classrooms-teaching, and controlling the social order. The study then elaborates on formal and informal instructional
strategies that teachers use to manage these tasks. The main foci of the study is to show that the effects of these different
instructional strategies on student achievements vary by grade level. The results suggest that the contexts of instruction
determine the magnitude and direction of the effects of instructional strategies on achievement. Positive effects on student
achievement appear when a functional congruence occurs between teachers' instructional strategies and the contexts wherein
they are used. The analyses suggest that changes in the cognitive, social, and institutional contexts of classrooms may change
the relative efficacy of specific instructional strategies. Consequently, researchers should pay more attention to the changes
in the sociology of classrooms during students' school careers.
This study was supported by a post-doctoral fellowship from the Fulbright Foundation and by a small research grant from The
Spencer Foundation. My wholehearted appreciation is given to the support I received from the Foundations. I am especially
grateful to Charles Bidwell from the University of Chicago, who encouraged me to pursue this study during my post-doctoral
visit in 1994–95. Discussions with Benjamin Wright and his warm support have been more than essential. The hospitality and
the academic environment at the NORC and the University of Chicago have done wonders to the fruition of ideas advanced in
this study. Yechezkel Dar and Ruth Butler made suggestions to the improvement of this article. Daniel Shalem and Rivka Berman
assisted with editorial as well as substantive comments. The reviewers ofSocial Psychology of Education insightfully suggested ways to improve the final version. 相似文献
200.
Norbert M. Samuelson 《Zygon》1996,31(4):695-710
Abstract. This article is a response to the 1994 Star Island conference on the "Decade of the Brain" from a Jewish perspective. After a brief introduction about the logical function of models and maps, I compare and contrast three models of the human: Ezekiel's vision of the chariot in the Hebrew Scriptures, Franz Rosenzweig's geometry of the human face in Der Stern der Erlosung (the Star of Redemption), and a standard anatomical picture of the human brain. Whereas Rosenzweigs face is seen to be compatible with Ezekiel's chariot, both are seen to be radically distinct from the implicit conception of what a human being is in modern medical science. I conclude with a suggestion that the differences are to be understood in terms of their different intended functions and express my hope for some new kind of model that will incorporate the functional advantages of both. 相似文献