首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   717篇
  免费   67篇
  国内免费   39篇
  2024年   2篇
  2023年   20篇
  2022年   10篇
  2021年   21篇
  2020年   43篇
  2019年   43篇
  2018年   42篇
  2017年   42篇
  2016年   36篇
  2015年   33篇
  2014年   35篇
  2013年   75篇
  2012年   17篇
  2011年   27篇
  2010年   15篇
  2009年   27篇
  2008年   42篇
  2007年   36篇
  2006年   28篇
  2005年   25篇
  2004年   22篇
  2003年   17篇
  2002年   12篇
  2001年   14篇
  2000年   14篇
  1999年   10篇
  1998年   11篇
  1997年   4篇
  1996年   5篇
  1995年   7篇
  1994年   4篇
  1993年   7篇
  1992年   7篇
  1991年   8篇
  1990年   5篇
  1989年   4篇
  1988年   3篇
  1986年   4篇
  1985年   2篇
  1984年   6篇
  1983年   1篇
  1982年   3篇
  1980年   1篇
  1979年   9篇
  1978年   6篇
  1977年   13篇
  1976年   3篇
  1975年   2篇
排序方式: 共有823条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
101.
In this paper two philosophical issues are discussed that hold special interest for empirical researchers studying happiness. The first issue concerns the question of how the psychological notion(s) of happiness invoked in empirical research relates to those traditionally employed by philosophers. The second concerns the question of how we ought to conceive of happiness, understood as a purely psychological phenomenon. With respect to the first, I argue that 'happiness', as used in the philosophical literature, has three importantly different senses that are often confused. Empirical research on happiness concerns only one of these senses, and serious misunderstandings about the significance of empirical results can arise from such confusion. I then argue that the second question is indeed philosophical and that, in order to understand the nature of (what I call) psychological happiness, we need first to determine what a theory of happiness is supposed to do: what are our theoretical and practical interests in the notion of happiness? I sketch an example of how such an inquiry might proceed, and argue that this approach can shed more light on the nature and significance of happiness (and related mental states) than traditional philosophical methods.  相似文献   
102.
不规则几何图形识别的取样首视点研究   总被引:5,自引:0,他引:5  
曹立人 《心理科学》2000,23(6):690-693
用实验方法对不规则几何图形的取样首视点进行研究。作业任务有认同与匹配二种,显示条件有良好与不良二种,显示方式有旋转与不旋转二种,绩效指标用反应时与错误指数二项。结果表明:首视点的分布是非均匀的,落在轮廓部位的概率最大,落在中央或某条特定边的概率极小。首视点分布的均匀度与作业难度有关,在作业难度较大的情况下,首视点分布趋于集中。多数情况下,首视点的置位对作业绩效的影响不大。  相似文献   
103.
104.
以往关于权力是否影响情绪的研究存在结果争议,这意味着可能存在其它因素的作用。本研究基于权力控制理论和社会距离理论,探究了社交情境中权力和反馈对情绪的影响。研究1采用经验取样法收集了140名被试五天内的1706段社交经历,研究2采用实验法考察了148名被试的社交经历。结果表明,权力和反馈对情绪存在交互影响:(1)当个体处于低权力情境时,反馈影响情绪,反馈越积极,情绪也越积极;(2)当个体获得积极反馈时,权力不影响情绪;当个体获得消极反馈时,权力影响情绪,权力越高,情绪相对更积极。本研究有助于厘清以往研究关于权力与情绪关系的争议。  相似文献   
105.
G.E.摩尔作为现代西方元伦理学的开创,他在建构其理论体系时所运用的方法不是单一的。而是针对伦理学的不同问题交错运用了直觉方法、绝对孤立法、有机统一原理和分析方法。他的这些方法对于分析伦理学的发展起了很大的作用,但终因其致命缺陷而使该流派走向衰落。  相似文献   
106.
Defining religion and finding ways to assess it in individual lives has long challenged psychologists of religion. At first, open‐ended questionnaires were used, but with the advent of modern statistical methods, a succession of religiosity scales was developed. But these usually brief scales were typically based on the preconceptions of their authors, who were overwhelmingly Protestant Christian and often conservative, much as were those who completed them. To provide a more adequate way of assessing “faith,” a term here encompassing both religious and nonreligious attitudes, a new assessment device was developed that incorporates the singular advantages of Q methodology. The Faith Q‐Sort consists of 101 statements that respondents sort on a nine‐category continuum, indicating the degree to which each statement describes himself or herself. Factor analysis based on correlations of the sorts rather than individual items yielded, for the initial group of participants, three major prototypes and five minor ones, accounting for 67 percent of the variance. Of the 42 participants, 31 proved to be exemplars of one or another of the eight prototypes. Subsequent explorations illustrate the wealth of possibilities the FQS offers, both as a research instrument and a counseling tool.  相似文献   
107.
While the Enlightenment promoted thinking for oneself independent of religious authority, the “Endarkenment” (Millgram 2015) concerns deference to a new authority: the specialist, a hyperspecializer. Nonspecialists need to defer to such authorities, as they are unable to understand their reasoning. Millgram describes how humans are capable of being serial hyperspecializers, able to move from one specialism to another. We support the basic thrust of Millgram’s position and seek to articulate how the core idea is deployed in very different ways in relation to extremely different philosophical areas. We attend to the issue of the degree of isolation of different specialists and urge greater emphasis on parallel hyperspecialization, which describes how different specialisms can be embodied in one person at one time.  相似文献   
108.
109.
110.
There is considerable philosophical dispute about what it takes for an action to be evil. The methodological assumption underlying this dispute is that there is a single, shared folk conception of evil action deployed amongst culturally similar people. Employing empirical research the authors undertook, this article suggests that this assumption is false. There exist, amongst the folk, numerous conceptions of evil action. Hence, the authors argue, philosophical research is most profitably spent in two endeavours. First, in determining which (if any) conception of evil action we have prudential or moral (or both) reason to deploy and, second, in determining whether we could feasibly come to adopt that conception as the single shared conception given our psychological make‐up and the content of the conceptions currently deployed.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号