全文获取类型
收费全文 | 1135篇 |
免费 | 59篇 |
国内免费 | 28篇 |
专业分类
1222篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 3篇 |
2024年 | 19篇 |
2023年 | 30篇 |
2022年 | 7篇 |
2021年 | 34篇 |
2020年 | 63篇 |
2019年 | 66篇 |
2018年 | 67篇 |
2017年 | 76篇 |
2016年 | 59篇 |
2015年 | 46篇 |
2014年 | 43篇 |
2013年 | 179篇 |
2012年 | 32篇 |
2011年 | 38篇 |
2010年 | 37篇 |
2009年 | 51篇 |
2008年 | 62篇 |
2007年 | 58篇 |
2006年 | 39篇 |
2005年 | 36篇 |
2004年 | 37篇 |
2003年 | 24篇 |
2002年 | 18篇 |
2001年 | 22篇 |
2000年 | 19篇 |
1999年 | 13篇 |
1998年 | 7篇 |
1997年 | 5篇 |
1996年 | 6篇 |
1995年 | 6篇 |
1994年 | 6篇 |
1993年 | 3篇 |
1992年 | 3篇 |
1991年 | 2篇 |
1990年 | 1篇 |
1989年 | 1篇 |
1988年 | 2篇 |
1985年 | 1篇 |
1984年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有1222条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
291.
ANDREI A. BUCKAREFF 《Theoria》2011,77(4):312-332
In this article, I challenge the dominant view of the importance of the debate over action‐individuation. On the dominant view, it is held that the conclusions we reach about action‐individuation make little or no difference for other debates in the philosophy of action, much less in other areas of philosophy. As a means of showing that the dominant view is mistaken, I consider the implications of accepting a given theory of action‐individuation for thinking about doxastic agency. In particular, I am interested in the implications for thinking about the variety of evaluative control we can exercise over the formation of our doxastic attitudes. I show that our assumptions about how to individuate actions matters for how we think about doxastic agency and, hence, the conclusions we reach about action‐individuation are of greater significance than some have thought. 相似文献
292.
293.
Processing the various features from different feature maps and modalities in coherent ways requires a dedicated integration mechanism (“the binding problem”). Many authors have related feature binding to conscious awareness but little is known about how tight this relationship really is. We presented subjects with asynchronous audiovisual stimuli and tested whether the two features were integrated. The results show that binding took place up to 350 ms feature-onset asynchronies, suggesting that integration covers a relatively wide temporal window. We also asked subjects to explicitly judge whether the two features would belong to the same or to the different events. Unsurprisingly, synchrony judgments decreased with increasing asynchrony. Most importantly, feature binding was entirely unaffected by conscious experience: features were bound whether they were experienced as occurring together or as belonging to a separate events, suggesting that the conscious experience of unity is not a prerequisite for, or a direct consequence of binding. 相似文献
294.
《Quarterly journal of experimental psychology (2006)》2013,66(11):2159-2171
The present study explored the role of the responding agent in a social context. To do so, we developed a compatibility task with socially relevant but task-irrelevant stimuli (own face, neutral face, and a friend's face). Participants were required to perform naming responses to coloured diamonds, while the faces were presented as irrelevant stimuli. We observed faster responses in face–name compatible than in incompatible conditions. When the task was distributed among two friends, we observed a compatibility effect in a joint go/no-go condition, in which both participants performed their go/no-go tasks together. In contrast, no compatibility effect was obtained in an individual go/no-go condition. Further, the experiment showed that this joint compatibility effect was based on the compatibility between the irrelevant face and the responding agent. This result demonstrates that features of the responding agent play a crucial role in the joint compatibility effect. 相似文献
295.
The Social Nature of Perception and Action 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
ABSTRACT— Humans engage in a wide range of social activities. Previous research has focused on the role of higher cognitive functions, such as mentalizing (the ability to infer others' mental states) and language processing, in social exchange. This article reviews recent studies on action perception and joint action suggesting that basic perception–action links are crucial for many social interactions. Mapping perceived actions to one's own action repertoire enables direct understanding of others' actions and supports action identification. Joint action relies on shared action representations and involves modeling of others' performance in relation to one's own. Taking the social nature of perception and action seriously not only contributes to the understanding of dedicated social processes but has the potential to create a new perspective on the individual mind and brain. 相似文献
296.
妇女健康一直是国际和欧洲组织的优先关注领域。为进一步改善欧洲妇女的健康状况,世界卫生组织欧洲区办事处组织编制了《欧洲妇女健康战略行动计划》。简要介绍了该战略行动计划的制定背景及主要内容,并总结其特点,为我国制定妇女健康战略行动计划提供一些启示。 相似文献
297.
Markos Valaris 《Philosophical Studies》2009,142(3):427-445
There is reason to expect a reasonable account of a priori knowledge to be linked with an account of the nature of conceptual
thought. Recent “two-dimensionalist” accounts of conceptual thought propose an extremely direct connection between the two:
on such views, being in a position to know a priori a large number of non-trivial propositions is a necessary condition of
concept-possession. In this paper I criticize this view, by arguing that it requires an implausibly internalist and intellectualist
conception of capacities we bring to bear in applying concepts in experience. Empirical concept-application depends on the
exercise of a variety of capacities, many of which can be grouped together under the general label “recognitional”. As I argue,
two-dimensionalism cannot accommodate a plausible account of such capacities. This suggests that the link between a priori
knowledge and the nature of conceptual thought is not as direct as twodimensionalists take it to be. I close by briefly sketching
a different way to think of that link.
相似文献
Markos ValarisEmail: |
298.
by John F. Haught 《Zygon》2010,45(1):213-220
Robert Russell's theological work has been a helpful stimulus to the task of understanding the meaning of divine action and providence in the age of science. He relates God's direct action "fundamentally" to the hidden domain of quantum events, and his theology of nature deserves careful attention. It is questionable, however, whether the term fundamental as applied to quantum events by physical science may be taken over by theology without more careful qualification than Russell offers. 相似文献
299.
本文尝试从现象学的生活世界观点出发,对黑格尔《精神现象学》之“感性确定性分析”中的动作性词语作一个解释学的解读工作,以便发掘出黑格尔辩证法之中介游戏或者间接同一性机制所以可能发生的动态的源初“地带”。 相似文献
300.
Christine M. Korsgaard 《The Journal of Ethics》1999,3(1):1-29
Plato and Kant advance a constitutional model of the soul, in which reason and appetite or passion have different structural and functional roles in the generation of motivation, as opposed to the familiar Combat Model in which they are portrayed as independent sources of motivation struggling for control. In terms of the constitutional model we may explain what makes an action different from an event. What makes an action attributable to a person, and therefore what makes it an action, is that it issues from the person's constitution, and therefore from the person as a whole, rather than from some force working on or in the person. This in turn implies an account of what makes an action good: what makes an action good is that it is deliberated upon and chosen in a way that unifies the person into a constitutional system. Through deliberative action we constitute ourselves as unified agents. Platonic justice and Kant's categorical imperative are shown to be normative standards for action because they are principles of self-constitution. 相似文献