全文获取类型
收费全文 | 4264篇 |
免费 | 61篇 |
专业分类
4325篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 35篇 |
2023年 | 42篇 |
2022年 | 41篇 |
2021年 | 73篇 |
2020年 | 86篇 |
2019年 | 119篇 |
2018年 | 155篇 |
2017年 | 164篇 |
2016年 | 180篇 |
2015年 | 124篇 |
2014年 | 146篇 |
2013年 | 486篇 |
2012年 | 218篇 |
2011年 | 251篇 |
2010年 | 147篇 |
2009年 | 143篇 |
2008年 | 191篇 |
2007年 | 159篇 |
2006年 | 143篇 |
2005年 | 112篇 |
2004年 | 137篇 |
2003年 | 135篇 |
2002年 | 106篇 |
2001年 | 79篇 |
2000年 | 87篇 |
1999年 | 63篇 |
1998年 | 51篇 |
1997年 | 41篇 |
1996年 | 27篇 |
1995年 | 26篇 |
1994年 | 26篇 |
1993年 | 22篇 |
1992年 | 42篇 |
1991年 | 30篇 |
1990年 | 49篇 |
1989年 | 43篇 |
1988年 | 43篇 |
1987年 | 22篇 |
1986年 | 32篇 |
1985年 | 31篇 |
1984年 | 24篇 |
1983年 | 22篇 |
1982年 | 19篇 |
1981年 | 13篇 |
1980年 | 10篇 |
1979年 | 17篇 |
1978年 | 13篇 |
1977年 | 8篇 |
1975年 | 8篇 |
1972年 | 12篇 |
排序方式: 共有4325条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
151.
Alphons M. G. van Dijk 《Journal of religion and health》1999,38(4):319-332
Increasing participation of Muslims and Hindus in church-state relations in the Netherlands is bringing about a slow change in the different cultural and historical backgrounds of non-indigenous religious traditions and in their self-esteem and religious attitudes. We may call this participation, and especially the changes it causes, a good example of Systemzwang, the systematic power of the dominant but historically grown social and cultural order in which newcomers are expected to fit. This process of external influence will be demonstrated by the example of the development of the traditional Hindu priest, the pandit, to a modern professional pastoral or Hindu-spiritual counsellor and by the mutual-learning process of the religiously different pastoral professionals in the semi-governmental service organizations. 相似文献
152.
This commentary distinguishes between the engineering-inspired formalisms used by Brackstone, M., and McDonald, M. (Transportation Research Part F (1999)) and the psychological knowledge of, and assumptions about human behaviour when car following. It outlines a preliminary mathematical model, based on psychological knowledge about car following behaviour by human drivers, which could be applied in traffic engineering, as a means of bringing these two ways of studying car following closer together. 相似文献
153.
Peter van Inwagen 《The Journal of Ethics》1999,3(4):343-351
In his classic paper, The Principle of Alternate Possibilities, Harry Frankfurt presented counterexamples to the principle named in his title: A person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise. He went on to argue that the falsity of the Principle of Alternate Possibilities (PAP) implied that the debate between the compatibilists and the incompatibilists (as regards determinism and the ability to do otherwise) did not have the significance that both parties had attributed to it -- since moral responsibility could exist even if no one was able to do otherwise. I have argued that even if PAP is false, there are other principles that imply that moral responsibility entails the ability to do otherwise, and that these principles are immune to Frankfurt-style counterexamples. Frankfurt has attempted to show that my arguments for this conclusion fail. This paper is a rejoinder to that reply; I argue that he has failed to show this. 相似文献
154.
A study is reported of an exocentric pointing task in all three dimensions, in near space, with only two visible luminous objects--a pointer and a target. The task of the subject was to aim a pointer at a target. The results clearly show that visual space is not isotropic, since every set direction appeared to consist of two independent components--one in the projection onto a frontoparallel plane (tilt), the other in depth (slant). The tilt component shows a general trend across subjects, an oblique effect, and can be judged monocularly. The slant component is symmetrical in the mid-sagittal plane, requires the use of binocular information, and shows considerable differences between subjects. These differences seem to depend on the amount of binocular information used by each subject. There was a remarkably high level of consistency in the exocentric pointing, despite the absence of environmental cues. The within-subject consistency in the settings of the pointer corresponds to a consistency of about 1 min of arc in disparity of its tip, even though the pointer and target are separated by more than 5 deg. 相似文献
155.
Anne van Hoof 《Developmental Review》1999,19(4):622
This article is a response to the commentaries of Waterman (this issue) and Berzonsky and Adams (this issue) on my review of the identity status field (van Hoof, this issue). The commentaries illustrate that the identity status researchers attribute different meanings to the identity statuses and identity status research; while Waterman finds it difficult to recognize the field in my review, Berzonsky and Adams agree with several of my conclusions. The two commentaries represent two pillars on which the status approach rests. The difference between the review and the commentaries is that the first includes both pillars, whereas each commentary consists primarily of a selective presentation of assumptions and data. This response focuses on two main points of the commentaries: (a) are the statuses sufficiently validated? and (b) to what extent are they suitable for testing developmental identity hypotheses? Using specific examples I show that the line of reasoning in the commentaries and the data proposed in support of these arguments in fact often support the conclusions of my review, for I demonstrate that the statuses are insufficiently validated and that the statuses are unsuitable for measuring identity development. These conclusions call for a fundamental revision of the identity status approach and a qualitative change in identity theory and research. Finally, the alternative approaches presented by Berzonsky and Adams are evaluated with respect to their contribution to an indispensable qualitative change in the identity status field. 相似文献
156.
157.
158.
In this study, cross-cultural differences in cognitive test scores are hypothesized to depend on a test's cultural complexity (Cultural Complexity Hypothesis: CCH), here conceptualized as its content familiarity, rather than on its cognitive complexity (Spearman's Hypothesis: SH). The content familiarity of tests assessing short-term memory, attention, working memory, and figural and verbal fluid reasoning, was manipulated by constructing test versions with an item content derived from either Afrikaans or Tswana culture in South Africa. Both test versions were administered to children of both cultures. The sample consisted of 161 urban Afrikaans, 181 urban, and 159 rural Tswana children (Mage = 9.37 years). Children generally performed best on the test version that was designed for their own group, particularly on the cognitively and culturally complex working memory and figural fluid reasoning tests. This relation between content familiarity and cognitive test performance supports CCH and disconfirms SH. 相似文献
159.
160.