首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   55862篇
  免费   2331篇
  国内免费   21篇
  58214篇
  2020年   675篇
  2019年   792篇
  2018年   1130篇
  2017年   1140篇
  2016年   1196篇
  2015年   854篇
  2014年   1032篇
  2013年   4839篇
  2012年   1930篇
  2011年   1932篇
  2010年   1152篇
  2009年   1184篇
  2008年   1667篇
  2007年   1629篇
  2006年   1494篇
  2005年   1237篇
  2004年   1278篇
  2003年   1229篇
  2002年   1166篇
  2001年   1924篇
  2000年   1797篇
  1999年   1341篇
  1998年   616篇
  1997年   529篇
  1996年   607篇
  1995年   552篇
  1994年   541篇
  1993年   527篇
  1992年   1106篇
  1991年   1017篇
  1990年   997篇
  1989年   958篇
  1988年   936篇
  1987年   862篇
  1986年   860篇
  1985年   907篇
  1984年   733篇
  1983年   628篇
  1979年   759篇
  1978年   566篇
  1975年   602篇
  1974年   683篇
  1973年   701篇
  1972年   606篇
  1971年   563篇
  1970年   485篇
  1969年   478篇
  1968年   612篇
  1967年   532篇
  1966年   508篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 46 毫秒
31.
32.
33.
abstract In Political Liberalism and later work John Rawls has recast his theory of justice as fairness in political terms. In order to illustrate the advantages of a liberal political approach to justice over liberal non‐political ones, Rawls discusses what kind of education might be required for future citizens of pluralistic and democratic societies. He advocates a rather minimal conception of civic education that he claims to derive from political liberalism. One group of authors has sided with Rawls’ political perspective and educational proposal, holding that a political approach and educational requirements that are not too demanding would have the advantage of being acceptable to a wide range of citizens with different religious, moral and philosophical perspectives. A second group of authors have criticized Rawls’ educational recommendations, holding that the production of a just society composed of reasonable citizens requires a more demanding civic education and, hence, that the political approach is not viable. The present paper argues that both groups are only partially right, and that there is a third way to understand civic education in Rawlsian terms, a way that is political but not minimal.  相似文献   
34.
Despite this virtue's history as an instrument of women's oppression, modesty, at its most basic, means voluntary restraint of one's power, undertaken for the sake of others. It is a mechanism that modifies unequal power relationships and encourages greater compassion and fairness. I use a Christian perspective with influences from Jewish and Muslim sources to examine modesty. The modest person, I argue, must be in relationship with others, must be honestly aware of her impacts on others, must be sensitive to those impacts, compassionate toward others, and willing to hold back for others' sakes. Moreover, modesty is not only a virtue that pertains to sexuality and clothing, but it also can promote virtuous environmental behavior, particularly as it leads to awareness of, and sensitivity to, the effects of everyday behaviors on vulnerable others.  相似文献   
35.
36.
37.
38.
Indiana statute allows police to seize firearms without a warrant if the officer believes a person meets the law's definition of “dangerous.” Review of the use of this law in Marion County (Indianapolis), Indiana, showed that prosecutors filed petitions in court to retain weapons seized by police under this law 404 times between 2006 and 2013. Police removed weapons from people due to identification of a risk of suicide (68%) or violence (21%), or the presence of psychosis (16%). The firearm seizures occurred in the context of domestic disputes in 28% of cases and intoxication was noted in 26% of cases. There were significant demographic differences in the circumstances of firearm seizures and the firearms seized. The seized firearms were retained by the court at the initial hearing in 63% of cases; this retention was closely linked to the defendant's failure to appear at the hearing. The court dismissed 29% of cases at the initial hearing, closely linked to the defendant's presence at the hearing. In subsequent hearings of cases not dismissed, the court ordered the destruction of the firearms in 72% of cases, all when the individual did not appear in court, and dismissed 24% of the cases, all when the individual was present at the hearing. Overall, the Indiana law removed weapons from a small number of people, most of whom did not seek return of their weapons. The firearm seizure law thus functioned as a months-long cooling-off period for those who did seek the return of their guns. Copyright © 2015 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.  相似文献   
39.
40.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号