全文获取类型
收费全文 | 94篇 |
免费 | 1篇 |
专业分类
95篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 2篇 |
2023年 | 1篇 |
2022年 | 4篇 |
2021年 | 6篇 |
2020年 | 5篇 |
2019年 | 10篇 |
2018年 | 6篇 |
2017年 | 2篇 |
2016年 | 5篇 |
2015年 | 3篇 |
2014年 | 3篇 |
2013年 | 7篇 |
2012年 | 7篇 |
2011年 | 2篇 |
2010年 | 1篇 |
2009年 | 2篇 |
2008年 | 1篇 |
2007年 | 4篇 |
2006年 | 5篇 |
2005年 | 4篇 |
2004年 | 4篇 |
2003年 | 2篇 |
2002年 | 1篇 |
2001年 | 2篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1991年 | 1篇 |
1983年 | 1篇 |
1982年 | 1篇 |
1975年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有95条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
81.
82.
A common finding is that there are response-repetition (RR) costs under task switching. Moreover, when the stimulus on the previous trial was congruent then RR costs are usually larger than when it was incongruent. This effect of the previous trial has been explained by assuming that a response category is generally inhibited after the execution of its corresponding response on the previous trial and that the amount of inhibition depends on the activation of the response category. However, up to now it was open which property of the response-category activation on the previous trial is crucial: the absolute activation of the correct response category or the activation difference between the alternative response categories. To differentiate between these two possibilities we compared RR costs after congruent, neutral, and incongruent trials. In two experiments we found similar RR costs after congruent and neutral trials, whereas the RR costs were smaller after incongruent trials. These results support the hypothesis that the amount of response inhibition is determined by the activation differences between the alternative response categories on the previous trial. 相似文献
83.
Tomasz Placek 《Synthese》2012,188(1):23-39
Against the background of the theory of branching space-times (BST), the paper sketches a concept of individuals. It discusses Kripkean modal intuitions concerning individuation, and, finally it addresses Lewis??s objections to branching individuals. 相似文献
84.
Tomasz Bigaj 《Erkenntnis》2012,76(1):1-22
David Lewis’s latest theory of causation defines the causal link in terms of the relation of influence between events. It
turns out, however, that one event’s influencing another is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for its being a cause
of that event. In the article one particular case of causality without influence is presented and developed. This case not
only serves as a counterexample to Lewis’s influence theory, but also threatens earlier counterfactual analyses of causation
by admitting a particularly troublesome type of preemption. The conclusion of the article is that Lewis’s influence method
of solving the preemption problem fails, and that we need a new and fresh approach to the cases of redundant causation if
we want to hold on to the counterfactual analysis of causation. 相似文献
85.
Knapska E Walasek G Nikolaev E Neuhäusser-Wespy F Lipp HP Kaczmarek L Werka T 《Learning & memory (Cold Spring Harbor, N.Y.)》2006,13(2):192-200
Understanding the function of the distinct amygdaloid nuclei in learning comprises a major challenge. In the two studies described herein, we used c-Fos immunolabeling to compare the engagement of various nuclei of the amygdala in appetitive and aversive instrumental training procedures. In the first experiment, rats that had already acquired a bar-pressing response to a partial food reinforcement were further trained to learn that an acoustic stimulus signaled either continuous food reinforcement (appetitive training) or a footshock (aversive training). The first training session of the presentation of the acoustic stimulus resulted in significant increases of c-Fos immunolabeling throughout the amygdala; however, the pattern of activation of the nuclei of the amygdala differed according to the valence of motivation. The medial part of the central amygdala (CE) responded, surprisingly, to the appetitive conditioning selectively. The second experiment was designed to extend the aversive versus appetitive conditioning to mice, trained either for place preference or place avoidance in an automated learning system (INTELLICAGE). Again, much more intense c-Fos expression was observed in the medial part of the CE after the appetitive training as compared to the aversive training. These data, obtained in two species and by means of novel experimental approaches balancing appetitive versus aversive conditioning, support the hypothesis that the central nucleus of the amygdala is particularly involved in appetitively motivated learning processes. 相似文献
86.
In list-method directed forgetting, people's ability to forget one of the sets of learned material is examined. Research shows that memory for to-be-forgotten items is impaired when assessed by a recall test and by recognition tests reliant on recollective processes. Retrieval inhibition and context-change mechanisms have been proposed to account for the directed forgetting effects and both of them account for the results obtained with recognition tests. However, the context change account makes a specific prediction that recollection is impaired by directed forgetting only if it makes use of contextual associations. In the present study, directed forgetting was examined with two types of recollection-based tasks making use of different types of associations, namely a list discrimination task utilising contextual associations and an associative recognition task utilising interitem associations. Consistent with the context change account, the costs of directed forgetting were observed in a list discrimination task and were not observed in an associative recognition task. The results indicate that impairment in recollection due to directed forgetting is not general and provide converging evidence to support the context-change account. 相似文献
87.
Wojciech Kulesza Dariusz Dolinski Mariola Kosim Tomasz Grzyb Paweł Muniak Dariusz Jemielniak 《Revue Européene de Psychologie Appliquée》2022,72(4):100767
BackgroundIn an experiment conducted in a natural setting, we test the link between mimicry, the amount of time during which the mimicry behavior takes place, and its impact on service quality.MethodsCable TV clients (n = 120) were randomly assigned to six experimental conditions (2 mimicry conditions: verbal mimicry vs. no mimicry x 3 interaction time: 5 vs. 10 vs. 15 minutes). Perceived service quality served as the dependent measurement.ResultsA main effect of mimicry was found on service quality: a cable TV representative was perceived more favorably when he mimicked the customer. Importantly, it was shown that even small portions of mimicry are beneficial, meaning that practitioners do not have to mimic someone for a long time to achieve benefits.ConclusionThe paper shows new benefits for the mimicker: more positive judgments by the mimickee regarding the impact on several different levels of service quality. 相似文献
88.
89.
Tomasz Bigaj 《Axiomathes》2005,15(4):599-619
The article deals with one particular problem created by the counterfactual analysis of causality à la Lewis, namely the context-sensitivity problem or, as I prefer to call it, the background condition problem. It appears that
Lewis’ counterfactual definition of causality cannot distinguish between proper causes and mere causal conditions – i.e. factors
necessary for the effect to occur, but commonly not seen as causally efficacious. The proposal is put forward to amend the
Lewis definition with a condition, based on the notion of cotenability, which would eliminate the problem. It is shown that
the corrected definition of causality leads to the transitivity of the causal relation. Possible objections to the proposed
solution, involving the assumption of indeterminism and the preemption cases, are given a thorough consideration. 相似文献
90.
Tomasz Połacik 《Studia Logica》1994,53(1):93-105
We consider propositional operators defined by propositional quantification in intuitionistic logic. More specifically, we investigate the propositional operators of the formA* :p q(p A(q)) whereA(q) is one of the following formulae: (¬¬q q) V ¬¬q, (¬¬q q) (¬¬q V ¬q), ((¬¬q q) (¬¬q V ¬q)) ((¬¬q q) V ¬¬q). The equivalence ofA*(p) to ¬¬p is proved over the standard topological interpretation of intuitionistic second order propositional logic over Cantor space.We relate topological interpretations of second order intuitionistic propositional logic over Cantor space with the interpretation of propositional quantifiers (as the strongest and weakest interpolant in Heyting calculus) suggested by A. Pitts. One of the merits of Pitts' interpretation is shown to be valid for the interpretation over Cantor space.Presented byJan Zygmunt 相似文献