全文获取类型
收费全文 | 415篇 |
免费 | 4篇 |
专业分类
419篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 2篇 |
2023年 | 6篇 |
2022年 | 5篇 |
2021年 | 1篇 |
2020年 | 14篇 |
2019年 | 17篇 |
2018年 | 12篇 |
2017年 | 13篇 |
2016年 | 23篇 |
2015年 | 14篇 |
2014年 | 20篇 |
2013年 | 47篇 |
2012年 | 27篇 |
2011年 | 23篇 |
2010年 | 12篇 |
2009年 | 25篇 |
2008年 | 22篇 |
2007年 | 12篇 |
2006年 | 17篇 |
2005年 | 14篇 |
2004年 | 11篇 |
2003年 | 11篇 |
2002年 | 8篇 |
2001年 | 6篇 |
2000年 | 10篇 |
1999年 | 13篇 |
1998年 | 2篇 |
1997年 | 3篇 |
1996年 | 6篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 2篇 |
1992年 | 2篇 |
1991年 | 3篇 |
1990年 | 1篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1982年 | 3篇 |
1980年 | 1篇 |
1977年 | 1篇 |
1976年 | 2篇 |
1967年 | 1篇 |
1963年 | 1篇 |
1962年 | 2篇 |
排序方式: 共有419条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
291.
Victoria Reyes-García Ronnie Babigumira Aili Pyhälä Sven Wunder Francisco Zorondo-Rodríguez Arild Angelsen 《Journal of Happiness Studies》2016,17(2):773-791
A commonality in the economics of happiness literature is that absolute income matters more for the subjective wellbeing of people at low income levels. In this article, we use a large sample of people in rural areas of developing countries with relatively low income levels to test whether subjective wellbeing an increasing function of absolute income in our sample, and to analyze the existence of adaptation and social comparison effects on subjective wellbeing. Our sample includes 6,973 rural households in 23 countries throughout Asia, Africa, and Latin America. The average total income per adult equivalent in our sample was US$ 1555, whereas levels of subjective wellbeing resembled levels found in previous research using cross-country data. We find that, despite low levels of absolute income, levels of subjective wellbeing of our respondents resemble levels found in previous research using cross-country data. We also find remarkable similarities in many of the determinants of subjective wellbeing previously tested. Our data show that absolute income covariates with subjective wellbeing, but—as for richer samples—the magnitude of the association is lower once we control for adaptation and social comparison. Finally, our results suggest that social comparison has a stronger effect than adaptation in explaining the subjective wellbeing of our sample. Our findings highlight the importance of adaptation and social comparison even at low levels of absolute income. 相似文献
292.
We argue that sensitivity to the distinction between the tensed notion of being something and the tensed notion of being located at the present time serves as a good antidote to confusions in debates about time and existence, in particular in the debate about how to characterise presentism, and saves us the trouble of going through unnecessary epicycles. Both notions are frequently expressed using the tensed verb ‘to exist’, making it systematically ambiguous. It is a commendable strategy to avoid using that verb altogether in these contexts and to use quantification and a location predicate instead.
相似文献293.
Sven Ove Hansson 《Studia Logica》2009,93(1):21-40
Two types of measures of probabilistic uncertainty are introduced and investigated. Dispersion measures report how diffused
the agent’s second-order probability distribution is over the range of first-order probabilities. Robustness measures reflect
the extent to which the agent’s assessment of the prior (objective) probability of an event is perturbed by information about
whether or not the event actually took place. The properties of both types of measures are investigated. The most obvious
type of robustness measure is shown to coincide with one of the major candidates for a dispersion measure, the mean square
deviation measure. 相似文献
294.
Sven Rosenkranz 《Erkenntnis》2003,58(3):353-378
Realists claim that, amongst the statements weunderstand, there are some which are true, yetwhose truth potentially transcends the limits ofwhat we can recognize. Dummett and othershave argued that this realist thesis is incompatiblewith an account of understanding in termsof recognitional capacities. But careful analysis revealsthat this contention is mistaken. Thealleged incompatibility presupposes the truth of ametaphysical principle which cannot bevindicated on the basis of an account of understanding.Realists have independent reason toreject this metaphysical principle, as it leads to a collapseof more modest forms of realisminto more contentious ones. According to moderate realism,we neither know that there areactually recognition-transcendent truthsnor do we know taht there are none. Pending apositive case for the metaphysical principle, thisagnosticism is sufficient to warrant therealists' key thesis, viz. that there arepotentially recognition-transcendent truths. Thusrealism, in its more moderate guise, turns outto be the default position. 相似文献
295.
Sven Ove hansson 《Topoi》2004,23(2):145-152
It is almost universally acknowledged that risks have to be weighed against benefits, but there are different ways to perform the weighing. In conventional risk analysis, collectivist risk-weighing is the standard. This means that an option is accepted if the sum of all individual benefits outweighs the sum of all individual risks. In practices originating in clinical medicine, such as ethical appraisals of clinical trials, individualist risk-weighing is the standard. This implies a much stricter criterion for risk acceptance, namely that the risk to which each individual is exposed should be outweighed by benefits for that same individual. The different choices of risk-weighing methods in different policy areas seem to have emerged from traditional thought patterns and social relations, rather than from explicit deliberations on possible justifications for the alternative ways to weigh risks against benefits. It is not obvious how the prevalent differences in risk-weighing practices can be reconstructed in terms of consistent underlying principles of preventive health or social priority-setting. 相似文献
296.
Prof. Dr. Sven Olaf Hoffmann Dipl.-Psych. Gerd Rudolf Bernhard Strauß 《Psychotherapeut》2008,53(1):4-16
Unwanted effects or even damage due to psychotherapy are largely neglected issues within psychotherapy research as compared to other fields. On the other hand, it is reasonable to assume that unwanted effects of a treatment which intends to influence patients into a positive direction are very likely. The rate of negative effects of psychotherapy (the deterioration effect according to Bergin) is consistently estimated to be 10% of all cases and shows this same rate in a variety of studies. This review highlights side effects of psychotherapy both on the part of the patients and of the therapists. It reports unwanted effects related to different psychotherapeutic methods, i.e. psychoanalysis, cognitive behaviour therapy, client-centered psychotherapy and – beyond these basic orientations – group psychotherapy. The paper also reports on negative effects of psychotherapy on an untreated partner. Finally, some proposals are given on how negative effects of psychotherapy could be diminished. The authors especially highlight the possibilities of changing the therapist, the treatment technique, or the theoretical treatment approach as a way to reduce negative effects. 相似文献
297.
Bestmann S 《Trends in cognitive sciences》2008,12(3):81-83
Transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) is the noninvasive method of choice for studying the causal relevance of a cortical area in the human brain. The success of TMS, however, is contrasted by limited insight into its mechanism of action. A recent study by Allen and colleagues offers stunning new insight into the physiological underpinnings of TMS. Their findings expand our understanding about a method that is widely used for stimulating research in the cognitive neurosciences. 相似文献
298.
299.
Sven Ove Hansson 《Philosophical Studies》1991,61(3):301-305
Conclusion Unlike the more commonly discussed paradoxes of deontic logic, the revenger's paradox is present not only in strong logics such as SDL, but also in much weaker logics that have been constructed to avoid the paradoxes of SDL. The paradox shows that any deontic logic with intersubstitutivity makes counter-intuitive truth assignments to some deontic expressions.However, the revenger's paradox does not pose as serious a problem as does Ross's paradox to the logics in which it occurs. A deontic logic in which Ross's paradox does not arise is preferable to one in which it does arise, even if the latter is subject to the revenger's paradox. 相似文献
300.
D. E. Anderson R. L. Ray S. Lease G. E. Billman D. C. Randall O. A. Smith C. A. Astley D. F. Taylor J. S. Turkkan A. H. Harris O. J. Andy V. Read A. Cowley D. Peeler J. B. Cabot D. M. Goff D. H. Cohen Thomas J. Carew W. H. Bridger G. A. Barr G. T. Schimmel G. B. Glavin F. L. Royer S. A. Corson E. O. Corson R. A. Lanese R. M. Andrysco W. C. Stanley Sven O. E. Ebbesson M. E. Bitterman R. Bruce Masterton Richard F. Thompson Bernard Lown Delos D. Wickens Carol D. Wickens B. H. Natelson T. M. Poandl R. McCarty C. F. Knapp J. M. Evans W. Wilson F. Freemon T. Ban W. Petrie C. Clinton W. S. Middleton 《Integrative psychological & behavioral science》1980,15(2):82-90