首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   35730篇
  免费   1468篇
  国内免费   10篇
  2020年   348篇
  2019年   495篇
  2018年   642篇
  2017年   667篇
  2016年   668篇
  2015年   478篇
  2014年   607篇
  2013年   2711篇
  2012年   1078篇
  2011年   1163篇
  2010年   692篇
  2009年   685篇
  2008年   1006篇
  2007年   978篇
  2006年   928篇
  2005年   835篇
  2004年   807篇
  2003年   746篇
  2002年   790篇
  2001年   1091篇
  2000年   998篇
  1999年   770篇
  1998年   416篇
  1997年   339篇
  1996年   338篇
  1992年   592篇
  1991年   581篇
  1990年   562篇
  1989年   575篇
  1988年   563篇
  1987年   528篇
  1986年   561篇
  1985年   605篇
  1984年   485篇
  1983年   457篇
  1982年   387篇
  1981年   369篇
  1979年   556篇
  1978年   408篇
  1976年   381篇
  1975年   457篇
  1974年   510篇
  1973年   529篇
  1972年   433篇
  1971年   405篇
  1970年   407篇
  1969年   427篇
  1968年   513篇
  1967年   457篇
  1966年   451篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
61.
62.
A taxonomy of part-whole or meronymic relations is developed to explain the ordinary English-speaker's use of the term “part of” and its cognates. The resulting classification yields six types of meronymic relations: 1. component-integral object (pedal-bike), 2. member-collection (ship-fleet), 3. portion-mass (slice-pie), 4. stuff-object (steel-car), 5. feature-activity (paying-shopping), and 6. place-area (Everglades-Florida). Meronymic relations ore further distinguished from other inclusion relations, such as spatial inclusion, and class inclusion, and from several other semantic relations: attribution, attachment, and ownership. This taxonomy is then used to explain cases of apparent intransitivity in merological syllogisms, and standard form syllogisms whose premises express different inclusion relations. The data suggest that intransitivities arise due to equivocations between different types of semantic relations. These results are then explained by means of the relation element theory which accounts for the character and behavior of semantic relations in terms of more primitive relational elements. The inferential phenomena observed are then explained by means of a single principle of element matching.  相似文献   
63.
64.
Abstract

This study builds on and extends previous sales leadership research by exploring sales professionals’ perceptions of effective leadership behaviors. Semistructured interviews with both sales leaders and salespeople working in a global enterprise software company were examined through a qualitative analysis. Results indicated that participants believed sales leadership played an important role in influencing sales performance. When asked to describe specific sales leader behaviors that best enable salesperson performance, sales professionals – both sales leaders and salespeople – overwhelmingly referenced coaching, followed by collaborating, championing, and customer engaging. We define and describe these four key sales leader behaviors and identify four potential mediating variables (trust, confidence, optimism, and resilience), from which emerges a conceptual framework of sales leader behaviors perceived to enable salesperson performance. We examine these four key sales leader behaviors and mediators in the broader context of leadership theory, particularly transformational, servant, authentic, and adaptive leadership theories. The key contribution of this study is the identification of a set of leader behaviors that are likely to be especially effective in modern sales organizations given that they originated from the perceptions of sales professionals themselves.  相似文献   
65.
There is an apparent tension in our everyday moral responsibility practices. On the one hand, it is commonly assumed that moral responsibility requires voluntary control: an agent can be morally responsible only for those things that fall within the scope of her voluntary control. On the other hand, we regularly praise and blame individuals for mental states and conditions that appear to fall outside the scope of their voluntary control, such as desires, emotions, beliefs, and other attitudes. In order to resolve this apparent tension, many philosophers appeal to a tracing principle to argue that agents are morally responsible (only) for those attitudes whose existence can be traced back, causally, to a voluntary action or omission in the past. My aim in this article is to critically evaluate this tracing strategy and to argue that it gives us a misguided picture of when and why we are morally responsible for our attitudes. I argue that we should accept a ‘judgment sensitivity’ condition of moral responsibility rather than a ‘voluntary control’ condition, and defend this account against various objections.  相似文献   
66.
67.
68.
69.
70.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号