全文获取类型
收费全文 | 111篇 |
免费 | 1篇 |
专业分类
112篇 |
出版年
2023年 | 1篇 |
2021年 | 1篇 |
2019年 | 6篇 |
2018年 | 2篇 |
2017年 | 4篇 |
2016年 | 3篇 |
2015年 | 1篇 |
2014年 | 3篇 |
2013年 | 12篇 |
2012年 | 11篇 |
2011年 | 4篇 |
2010年 | 4篇 |
2009年 | 3篇 |
2008年 | 13篇 |
2007年 | 3篇 |
2006年 | 4篇 |
2005年 | 3篇 |
2003年 | 4篇 |
2002年 | 2篇 |
2000年 | 2篇 |
1999年 | 6篇 |
1998年 | 3篇 |
1997年 | 1篇 |
1996年 | 2篇 |
1995年 | 2篇 |
1994年 | 1篇 |
1993年 | 1篇 |
1992年 | 1篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1987年 | 3篇 |
1983年 | 1篇 |
1981年 | 1篇 |
1980年 | 1篇 |
1978年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有112条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
91.
92.
Brown R González R Zagefka H Manzi J Cehajic S 《Journal of personality and social psychology》2008,94(1):75-90
Three studies examined the hypothesis that collective guilt and shame have different consequences for reparation. In 2 longitudinal studies, the ingroup was nonindigenous Chileans (Study 1: N = 124/120, lag = 8 weeks; Study 2: N = 247/137, lag = 6 months), and the outgroup was Chile's largest indigenous group, the Mapuche. In both studies, it was found that collective guilt predicted reparation attitudes longitudinally. Collective shame had only cross-sectional associations with reparation and no direct longitudinal effects. In Study 2, collective shame moderated the longitudinal effects of collective guilt such that the effects of guilt were stronger for low-shame respondents. In Study 3 (N = 193 nonindigenous Chileans), the cross-sectional relationships among guilt, shame, and reparation attitudes were replicated. The relationship between shame and reparation attitudes was mediated by a desire to improve the ingroup's reputation. 相似文献
93.
94.
95.
The importance of social context in affecting attention has recently been highlighted by the finding that the presence of
a passive, nonevaluative confederate can improve selective attention. The underlying mechanism, however, remains unclear.
In this paper, we argue that social facilitation can be caused by distractor inhibition. Two distinct sources of evidence
are provided from an experiment employing the Stroop task with and without social presence. First, analysis of the response
time (RT) distribution indicates that interference is reduced at relatively long RTs. This is consistent with an inhibitory
mechanism, whose effects build up slowly. Further support is provided by showing that social facilitation is prevented by
using short response-to-stimulus intervals that are thought to reduce cognitive control processes. 相似文献
96.
97.
Leslie Rupert Herrenkohl Jiyoung Lee Fan Kong Susie Nakamura Kimia Imani Kari Nasu 《认知与教导》2019,37(3):327-348
AbstractPrevious research demonstrates that social and interpersonal factors, more than academic preparation, affect decisions by under-represented students to stay in or to leave STEM fields. Yet, much of the theorizing about STEM learning in higher education begins with conceptual and epistemological dimensions. We make the case for a new theoretical framework, a learning humanities, that begins with relationships. From this relational starting point, we locate STEM knowers as actors in relationships who become answerable for their STEM knowledge and take wise actions from this place. We then use this framework to analyze learning for STEM undergraduates involved in the STUDIO: Build Our World program, an afterschool mentoring program for low-income, immigrant, and refugee youth of color. Drawing on narrative and ethnographic analyses of data from 12 focal mentors, we found that mentors developed 3 focal practices identified by Edwards, relational expertise, common knowledge, and relational agency through their efforts to create the best possible program for youth. This built mentors’ sense of answerability and a capacity for wise action within and outside of STUDIO. We argue that this theoretical stance provides new ways to conceptualize the nature, purpose, and outcomes of STEM learning for historically non-dominant STEM undergraduates’ learning. 相似文献
98.
99.
Joke Meeus Javiera Paredes Mayor Roberto González Rupert Brown Jorge Manzi 《European journal of social psychology》2017,47(3):289-303
In three experiments (N = 56, 99, and 225), we showed that racial phenotypicality bias characterizes educational expectations for Chilean mestizo students: participants displayed more positive educational expectations for light complexioned than for dark complexioned high school students. In Study 1, with male high school target students, the relation between racial phenotypic appearance and educational expectations was mediated by differences in perceived competence. Study 2 suggests that the gender of the target student did not influence the occurrence of racial phenotypicality bias. Study 3 showed that racial phenotypicality bias occurs in both university students and high school teachers' judgements. Although socioeconomic background of the target student partially explained the effects of racial phenotypic appearance (especially in teachers), the latter exerted an additional and independent influence on educational expectations. These results underline the fact that effects of racial phenotypicality bias should not be overlooked in the educational domain. As mediational analyses suggested, these effects only partly occur because of stereotypical associations between racial phenotypic appearance and socioeconomic background, but also because of stereotypical associations between racial phenotypic appearance and attributed competence. 相似文献
100.
Robert D. Rupert 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2013,91(3):559-562
A main thread of the debate over mathematical realism has come down to whether mathematics does explanatory work of its own in some of our best scientific explanations of empirical facts. Realists argue that it does; anti-realists argue that it doesn't. Part of this debate depends on how mathematics might be able to do explanatory work in an explanation. Everyone agrees that it's not enough that there merely be some mathematics in the explanation. Anti-realists claim there is nothing mathematics can do to make an explanation mathematical; realists think something can be done, but they are not clear about what that something is. I argue that many of the examples of mathematical explanations of empirical facts in the literature can be accounted for in terms of Jackson and Pettit's [1990] notion of program explanation, and that mathematical realists can use the notion of program explanation to support their realism. This is exactly what has happened in a recent thread of the debate over moral realism (in this journal). I explain how the two debates are analogous and how moves that have been made in the moral realism debate can be made in the mathematical realism debate. However, I conclude that one can be a mathematical realist without having to be a moral realist. 相似文献