首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   188435篇
  免费   8359篇
  国内免费   155篇
  2020年   2784篇
  2019年   3441篇
  2018年   3667篇
  2017年   4114篇
  2016年   4707篇
  2015年   3938篇
  2014年   4814篇
  2013年   23457篇
  2012年   5013篇
  2011年   4304篇
  2010年   4103篇
  2009年   4864篇
  2008年   4439篇
  2007年   4070篇
  2006年   4503篇
  2005年   4414篇
  2004年   3895篇
  2003年   3478篇
  2002年   3356篇
  2001年   4048篇
  2000年   3911篇
  1999年   3659篇
  1998年   2894篇
  1997年   2734篇
  1996年   2648篇
  1995年   2462篇
  1994年   2420篇
  1993年   2393篇
  1992年   3043篇
  1991年   2851篇
  1990年   2690篇
  1989年   2554篇
  1988年   2540篇
  1987年   2524篇
  1986年   2561篇
  1985年   2760篇
  1984年   2755篇
  1983年   2501篇
  1982年   2447篇
  1981年   2425篇
  1980年   2253篇
  1979年   2530篇
  1978年   2330篇
  1977年   2249篇
  1976年   2054篇
  1975年   2237篇
  1974年   2321篇
  1973年   2253篇
  1972年   1831篇
  1971年   1729篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
191.
192.
193.
To understand how individuals adapt to and anticipate each other in joint tasks, we employ a bidirectional delay–coupled dynamical system that allows for mutual adaptation and anticipation. In delay–coupled systems, anticipation is achieved when one system compares its own time‐delayed behavior, which implicitly includes past information about the other system’s behavior, with the other system’s instantaneous behavior. Applied to joint music performance, the model allows each system to adapt its behavior to the dynamics of the other. Model predictions of asynchrony between two simultaneously produced musical voices were compared with duet pianists’ behavior; each partner performed one voice while auditory feedback perturbations occurred at unpredictable times during live performance. As the model predicted, when auditory feedback from one musical voice was removed, the asynchrony changed: The pianist’s voice that was removed anticipated (preceded) the actions of their partner. When the auditory feedback returned and both musicians could hear each other, they rapidly returned to baseline levels of asynchrony. To understand how the pianists anticipated each other, their performances were fitted by the model to examine change in model parameters (coupling strength, time‐delay). When auditory feedback for one or both voices was removed, the fits showed the expected decrease in coupling strength and time‐delay between the systems. When feedback about the voice(s) returned, the coupling strength and time‐delay returned to baseline. These findings support the idea that when people perform actions together, they do so as a coupled bidirectional anticipatory system.  相似文献   
194.
195.
196.
197.
198.
Human communication is thoroughly context bound. We present two experiments investigating the importance of the shared context, that is, the amount of knowledge two interlocutors have in common, for the successful emergence and use of novel conventions. Using a referential communication task where black‐and‐white pictorial symbols are used to convey colors, pairs of participants build shared conventions peculiar to their dyad without experimenter feedback, relying purely on ostensive‐inferential communication. Both experiments demonstrate that access to the visual context promotes more successful communication. Importantly, success improves cumulatively, supporting the view that pairs establish conventional ways of using the symbols to communicate. Furthermore, Experiment 2 suggests that dyads with access to the visual context successfully adapt the conventions built for one color space to another color space, unlike dyads lacking it. In linking experimental pragmatics with language evolution, the study illustrates the benefits of exploring the emergence of linguistic conventions using an ostensive‐inferential model of communication.  相似文献   
199.
200.
Do the conditions under which promises are made determine whether they ought to be kept? Philosophers have placed a number of conditions on promising which, they hold, must be met in order to make promise-keeping obligatory. In so doing, they have distinguished valid promises from invalid promises and justified promises from promises that are not justified. Considering such conditions, one by one, we argue that they are mistaken. In the first place, the conditions they lay down are not necessary for either valid or justified promise-making. In the second place, promises need not meet such conditions in order to create moral obligations. In general, such analyses of promising fail because they suffer from a confusion between promise-making and promise-keeping. Philosophers have wrongly supposed that obligations to keep promises are dependent upon, or derivable from, the quality of the promises themselves, at the time they are made, instead of focusing on conditions that must be satisfied at the time when promises are supposed to be kept. It is not the quality of a promise that determines an obligation to keep it but the rightness or wrongness of performing the promised act.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号