全文获取类型
收费全文 | 7972篇 |
免费 | 124篇 |
专业分类
8096篇 |
出版年
2020年 | 82篇 |
2019年 | 96篇 |
2018年 | 137篇 |
2017年 | 142篇 |
2016年 | 165篇 |
2015年 | 128篇 |
2014年 | 132篇 |
2013年 | 783篇 |
2012年 | 274篇 |
2011年 | 284篇 |
2010年 | 185篇 |
2009年 | 217篇 |
2008年 | 284篇 |
2007年 | 314篇 |
2006年 | 284篇 |
2005年 | 258篇 |
2004年 | 246篇 |
2003年 | 302篇 |
2002年 | 267篇 |
2001年 | 109篇 |
2000年 | 108篇 |
1999年 | 132篇 |
1998年 | 103篇 |
1997年 | 117篇 |
1996年 | 116篇 |
1995年 | 126篇 |
1994年 | 97篇 |
1993年 | 119篇 |
1992年 | 104篇 |
1991年 | 97篇 |
1990年 | 77篇 |
1989年 | 79篇 |
1988年 | 84篇 |
1987年 | 98篇 |
1986年 | 80篇 |
1985年 | 91篇 |
1984年 | 114篇 |
1983年 | 120篇 |
1982年 | 109篇 |
1981年 | 106篇 |
1980年 | 109篇 |
1979年 | 107篇 |
1978年 | 118篇 |
1977年 | 108篇 |
1976年 | 119篇 |
1975年 | 91篇 |
1974年 | 96篇 |
1973年 | 92篇 |
1972年 | 59篇 |
1971年 | 48篇 |
排序方式: 共有8096条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
131.
132.
133.
Word repetitions in sentence recognition 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
When some items on a list are strengthened by extra study time or repetitions, recognition of other, unrelated, list items is not harmed (Ratcliff, Clark, & Shiffrin, 1990). Shiffrin, Ratcliff, and Clark (1990) accounted for this list-strength finding with a model assuming that different items are stored separately in memory, but that repetitions are accumulated together into a single stronger memory trace. Repeating words in the context of different sentences might cause separate storage of the repetitions of a given word, because either word or sentence traces are stored separately. Separate storage would, in effect, convert a list-strength manipulation into a list-length manipulation and thereby induce a positive list-strength effect. In Experiment 1, this result was produced for single-word recognition and for two types of sentence recognition. In Experiment 2, both words and sentences were repeated together, which should have caused repetitions to be stored in a single, stronger, trace. As expected, the list-strength effect was eliminated. A sentence trace model was fit to the data, supporting the account of Shiffrin et al. (1990) and supporting an account of word and sentence recognition in which activation is summed for representations of all list items. The results from the two studies are inconsistent with most current models of memory (as shown by the theoretical analyses of Shiffrin et al., 1990) and pose an additional challenge for theory. 相似文献
134.
135.
Recently critics have faulted American business schools for failing to impart to their students an understanding of ethics and its role in business. In this paper, we agree and attribute this situation, at least in part, to the need for a vocabulary of ethics and a failure to communicate Adam Smith's moral orientation to capitalism. So long as business schools fail to recognize explicitly that Smith, whoseThe Wealth of Nations serves as an intellectual backdrop for business school curricula, did in fact provide a place for ethics in capitalist economic relations (indeed, some would argue a dominant place), they will continue to advocate implicitly the theory of amorality in business—the idea that ethics has no place in business. By examining Smith's ethical arguments we can explicate the moral underpinnings of stakeholder analysis, a currently popular approach to management decision-making.Although we will use ethics and morality interchangeably in this paper, there is a distinction to be made. Ethics is the branch of philosophy concentrating on morality. Morality pertains to what is right and wrong. 相似文献
136.
Kitchener RF 《Ethics & behavior》1991,1(4):221-238
In this article, I am concerned with the ethical foundations of behavior therapy, that is, with the normative ethics and the meta-ethics underlying behavior therapy. In particular, I am concerned with questions concerning the very possibilty of providing an ethical justification for things done in the context of therapy. Because behavior therapists must be able to provide an ethical justification for various actions (if the need arises), certain meta-ethical views widely accepted by behavior therapists must be abandoned; in particular, one must give up ethical subjectivism, ethical skepticism, and ethical relativism. An additional task is to show how it is possible to provide a nonsubjective, nonskeptical, and nonrelativistic moral justification for an ethical statement. Although this is a monumental task, I provide a rough sketch of such a model, one that is congenial to the value judgments underlying behavior therapy. 相似文献
137.
Richard A McCormick 《Kennedy Institute of Ethics journal》1991,1(4):303-305
...In conclusion, let me agree with Robertson that reasonable persons may indeed disagree on concrete conclusions touching preembryo freezing, discard, research, and diagnosis. But it is one of the challenges to reasonable people to give reasons for their conclusions. When Robertson notes that preembryo research "has been found acceptable by most bodies that have examined the subject," he leaves unstated the fact that many of these bodies have not given reasons for their conclusions. This is especially true of the Warnock Committee. It is definitely not true of John Robertson. He has attempted to give analytic support for his rather permissive positions. I find this support too fragile for its assigned task, though I hasten to say that this does not mean that only a totally prohibitive position is defensible or is mine. Prima facie still means prima facie. 相似文献
138.
139.
Richard Degerman 《Psychometrika》1982,47(4):523-527
A procedure is described for orienting the nodes of a binary tree to maximize the Kendall rank order correlation (tau) between node order and a given external criterion. The procedure is computationally efficient and is based on application of an ordered set of node tests. 相似文献
140.