全文获取类型
收费全文 | 20323篇 |
免费 | 4篇 |
专业分类
20327篇 |
出版年
2022年 | 1篇 |
2020年 | 3篇 |
2018年 | 3485篇 |
2017年 | 2811篇 |
2016年 | 2240篇 |
2015年 | 188篇 |
2014年 | 69篇 |
2013年 | 59篇 |
2012年 | 557篇 |
2011年 | 2376篇 |
2010年 | 2510篇 |
2009年 | 1467篇 |
2008年 | 1694篇 |
2007年 | 2166篇 |
2006年 | 21篇 |
2005年 | 208篇 |
2004年 | 160篇 |
2003年 | 107篇 |
2002年 | 57篇 |
2001年 | 28篇 |
2000年 | 51篇 |
1999年 | 14篇 |
1998年 | 19篇 |
1997年 | 16篇 |
1996年 | 7篇 |
1995年 | 1篇 |
1994年 | 2篇 |
1990年 | 7篇 |
1976年 | 1篇 |
1974年 | 1篇 |
1969年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
51.
Brad J. Kallenberg 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2012,71(1):55-73
Careful readers of Wittgenstein tend to overlook the significance his engineering education had for his philosophy; this despite
Georg von Wright’s stern admonition that “the two most important facts to remember about Wittgenstein were, firstly, that
he was Viennese, and, secondly, that he was an engineer.” Such oversight is particularly tempting for those of us who come
to philosophy late, having first been schooled in math and science, because our education tricks us into thinking we understand
engineering by extension. But we do not. I will illustrate this common tendency to misread Wittgenstein by examining three
engineering concepts that have little significance for science but played important roles in Wittgenstein’s philosophical
thinking. These are: method of projection, dynamical similarity, and satisfactoriness. The upshot of this analysis will be
a strong challenge to the myth of his putative fideism because neither fideism nor its contrary simply would have occurred
to Wittgensteinthe-engineer. 相似文献
52.
Mikel Burley 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2012,71(1):21-37
This paper critically discusses D. Z. Phillips’ use of literary works as a resource for philosophical reflection on religion.
Beginning by noting Phillips’ suggestion, made in relation to Waiting for Godot, that the possibilities of meaning that we see in a literary work can reveal something of our own religious sensibility,
I then proceed to show what we learn about Phillips from his readings of certain works by Larkin, Tennyson, and Wharton. Through
exploring alternative possible readings, I argue that, although Phillips’ discussions are of considerable philosophical interest,
they undermine his claim to be deploying a purely contemplative hermeneutical method. 相似文献
53.
John Cattich 《Pastoral Psychology》2012,61(2):179-195
This study explores how parts of the clergy system interact in response to congregational and familial demands. Qualitative
analysis of semi-structured interviews with twenty-four clergy and their spouses identified three clergy system models based
on the spiritual meaning and relational dynamics between the clergy, their spouses, and the congregations: The living sacrifice model emphasizes service to the congregation at the expense of personal and familial needs; the faithful spouse and parent model focuses on family needs over the congregation and practices several disciplines to maintain such a focus; and the peacemaker model seeks as much as possible to satisfy their congregation and their family by intentionally juggling their demands. Results
illustrate how relational processes and spiritual meaning contribute to how clergy systems respond to systemic demands and
pressures. 相似文献
54.
Michelle L. Thomas 《Pastoral Psychology》2012,61(1):99-112
The purpose of this study is to examine the relationships among variables identified in research literature as obstacles and
benefits to interprofessional collaboration-- academic education, interprofessional education, teamwork and communication
skills, and trust---as it relates to the participation of clergypersons in interprofessional collaborative practice. The sample
consisted of ordained Christian clergypersons in Florida who voluntarily completed a survey questionnaire. Standard and stepwise
multiple regression was applied to analyze the data. The model accounts for 25% of the variation of interprofessional collaborative
practice. Results also revealed that the education variables explained significantly 20% of the variance of interprofessional
collaborative practice. 相似文献
55.
Chris Tucker 《Philosophical Studies》2012,157(3):323-340
Does inferential justification require the subject to be aware that her premises support her conclusion? Externalists tend to answer “no” and internalists tend to answer “yes”. In fact, internalists often hold the strong higher-level requirement that an argument justifies its conclusion only if the subject justifiably believes that her premises support her conclusion. I argue for a middle ground. Against most externalists, I argue that inferential justification requires that one be aware that her premises support her conclusion. Against many internalists, I argue that this higher-level awareness needn’t be doxastic or justified. I also argue that the required higher-level awareness needn’t be caused in some appropriate way, e.g. by a reliable or properly functioning faculty. I suspect that this weaker higher-level requirement is overlooked because, at first glance, it seems absurd to allow nondoxastic, unjustified, and unreliably-caused higher-level awareness to contribute to inferential justification. One of the central goals of this paper is to explain how such weak awareness can make an essential contribution to inferential justification. 相似文献
56.
Todd R. Long 《Philosophical Studies》2012,157(2):251-266
Michael Bergmann seeks to motivate his externalist, proper function theory of epistemic justification by providing three objections
to the mentalism and mentalist evidentialism characteristic of nonexternalists such as Richard Feldman and Earl Conee. Bergmann
argues that (i) mentalism is committed to the false thesis that justification depends on mental states; (ii) mentalism is
committed to the false thesis that the epistemic fittingness of an epistemic input to a belief-forming process must be due
to an essential feature of that input, and, relatedly, that mentalist evidentialism is committed to the false thesis that
the epistemic fittingness of doxastic response B to evidence E is an essential property of B–E; and (iii) mentalist evidentialism
is “unmotivated”. I object to each argument. The argument for (i) begs the question. The argument for (ii) suffers from the
fact that mentalist evidentialists are not committed to the consequences claimed for them; nevertheless, I show that there
is, in the neighborhood, a substantive dispute concerning the nature of doxastic epistemic fittingness. That dispute involves
what I call “Necessary Fittingness”, the view that, necessarily, exactly one (at most) doxastic attitude (belief, or disbelief, or suspension of judgment) toward a proposition is epistemically fitting with respect to a person’s total evidence at any time. Reflection on my super-blooper
epistemic design counterexamples to Bergmann’s proper function theory reveals both the plausibility of Necessary Fittingness
and a good reason to deny (iii). Mentalist evidentialism is thus vindicated against the objections. 相似文献
57.
Cultures shape the types of goals that students pursue in the classroom. However, research in achievement goal theory seems
to have neglected this cultural aspect with its exclusive focus on individualistically-based goals such as mastery and performance
goals. This emphasis on mastery and performance goals may reflect Western individualist psychological thinking. Thus, social
goals, which may be more salient in collectivist cultures, are relatively neglected. There is a dearth of studies investigating
the role of social goals in academic motivation, and the few studies that did explore them are somewhat problematic. This
paper reviews research done within the achievement goal theory, considers the need for more studies on social goals, and concludes
with the argument that social goals are important in understanding student motivation especially in collectivist cultures. 相似文献
58.
Bowins BE 《American journal of psychoanalysis》2012,72(2):152-165
Based on the evolution of human intelligence and the tremendous cognitive capacities arising from it, we have an innate tendency for the extreme thought content, thought form, and sensory perceptions of psychosis. During the conscious and awake state, cognitive regulatory control processes block these more extreme variants to facilitate reality congruency necessary for adaptive functioning. While asleep there is no need for reality congruency and the cognitive regulatory control processes are deactivated allowing psychotic equivalents to be expressed in dreams. This paper helps synthesize the two dominant perspectives regarding the etiology of psychosis: the neuroscience defect perspective and the psychoanalytic motivational perspective. Regarding the former, defective cognitive regulation arising from certain conditions, such as the deficit state of schizophrenia, allows extreme cognitive distortions, thought form variants, and sensory perceptual experiences to intrude into the conscious and awake state, thereby producing psychosis. Consistent with the psychoanalytic motivational perspective, defensive processes can motivate extreme cognitive distortions, thought form variants and sensory perceptual experiences, and also facilitate their expression by deactivating the relevant cognitive regulatory control processes. 相似文献
59.
60.
L Mélèse 《American journal of psychoanalysis》2012,72(3):223-241
In this paper, the author presents a summary of a brief treatment with a young woman, suffering from severe epileptic illness, which describes the mutuality of cross-transferences of deep and intense feelings and the unorthodox way to receive, to take in persons affected with critical phenomena. This treatment was deeply influenced by the traumatic triad, borrowed from Ferenczi: "amnesia, anaesthesia, aboulia," the ways of forgetting (or erasing) the past/the present/the future. The investigation led us to clarify, on the one hand, the incestophilic-or perhaps incestuous-source in the family, and on the other, the burdensome and tragic genealogy and history of each parent. At the end of this short treatment, which took place at a frequency of one session a week (with the patient sitting, standing, lying on the floor; with sometimes severe fits, deliria, threats; bringing of letters, texts, drawings; and a few phone calls), there was an alleviation of the critical phenomena and revival. 相似文献