首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   589篇
  免费   75篇
  国内免费   60篇
  2024年   1篇
  2023年   7篇
  2022年   6篇
  2021年   22篇
  2020年   21篇
  2019年   12篇
  2018年   30篇
  2017年   30篇
  2016年   20篇
  2015年   27篇
  2014年   22篇
  2013年   69篇
  2012年   43篇
  2011年   39篇
  2010年   39篇
  2009年   38篇
  2008年   46篇
  2007年   54篇
  2006年   28篇
  2005年   47篇
  2004年   24篇
  2003年   14篇
  2002年   19篇
  2001年   2篇
  2000年   8篇
  1999年   7篇
  1998年   6篇
  1997年   2篇
  1996年   4篇
  1995年   4篇
  1994年   3篇
  1993年   2篇
  1992年   1篇
  1991年   3篇
  1990年   4篇
  1988年   2篇
  1987年   1篇
  1986年   1篇
  1985年   1篇
  1984年   3篇
  1983年   1篇
  1979年   2篇
  1978年   3篇
  1976年   1篇
  1975年   2篇
  1974年   2篇
  1971年   1篇
排序方式: 共有724条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
591.
Perceptual experiences inform us about objective properties of things in our environment. But they also have perspectival character in the sense that they differ phenomenally when objects are viewed from different points of view. Contemporary representationalists hold, at a minimum, that phenomenal character supervenes on representational content. Thus, in order to account for perspectival character, they need to indentify a type of representational content that changes in appropriate ways with the perceiver’s point of view. Many representationlists, including Shoemaker and Lycan, argue that such contents are best construed in terms of mind-dependent properties. Other representationalists, including Tye and Dretske, hold that these contents involve only mind-independent properties. Susanna Schellenberg has recently developed an account of perceptual experience that would serve these latter representationalists extremely well. She suggests that we can do justice to the perspectival character of perceptual experience by appeal to representations of a certain type of relational properties, so-called ‘situation-dependent properties.’ In this paper, I critically engage with Schellenberg’s proposal in order to show how mind-independent representationalists can explain perspectival character. I argue that appeal to situation-dependent properties is problematic. I then show that mind-independent representationalists can account for perspectical character by means of scenario contents in Christopher Peacocke’s sense.  相似文献   
592.
In 2 experiments, we investigated the effect of presentation rate on both immediate (5 min) and delayed (2 days) cued recall of paired associates. Word pairs were presented for a total of 16 s per pair, with presentation duration of individual presentations varying from 1 to 16 s. In Experiment 1, participants studied word pairs with presentation rates of 16 × 1 s, 8 × 2 s, 4 × 4 s, 2 × 8 s, or 1 × 16 s. A nonmonotonic relationship was found between presentation rate and cued recall performance. Both short (e.g., 1 s) and long (e.g., 16 s) presentation durations resulted in poor immediate and delayed recall, compared with intermediate presentation durations. In Experiment 2, we replicated these general findings. Moreover, we showed that the 4 s condition resulted in less proportional forgetting than the 1 s and the 16 s conditions.  相似文献   
593.
从公立医疗服务准公共产品特性和医疗服务的性质两个方面,强调了政府对公立医院补偿的必要性和合理性,并指出了政府补偿中存在财政补偿不足、缺乏补偿标准、监管不力等问题.同时,针对政府补偿现状提出了加大政府对公立医院的投入;设计科学合理的公立医院财政补偿制度;加强对公立医院财政投入资金的监管等政策建议.  相似文献   
594.
Even without feedback, test practice enhances delayed performance compared to study practice, but the size of the effect is variable across studies. We investigated the benefit of testing, separating initially retrievable items from initially nonretrievable items. In two experiments, an initial test determined item retrievability. Retrievable or nonretrievable items were subsequently presented for repeated study or test practice. Collapsing across items, in Experiment 1, we obtained the typical cross-over interaction between retention interval and practice type. For retrievable items, however, the cross-over interaction was quantitatively different, with a small study benefit for an immediate test and a larger testing benefit after a delay. For nonretrievable items, there was a large study benefit for an immediate test, but one week later there was no difference between the study and test practice conditions. In Experiment 2, initially nonretrievable items were given additional study followed by either an immediate test or even more additional study, and one week later performance did not differ between the two conditions. These results indicate that the effect size of study/test practice is due to the relative contribution of retrievable and nonretrievable items.  相似文献   
595.
自闭症儿童的中心信息整合及其与心理理论的关系   总被引:9,自引:0,他引:9  
桑标  任真  邓赐平 《心理科学》2006,29(1):52-56
研究用积木测验和镶嵌图形测验测量中心信息整合,用5个信念任务测量心理理论能力,比较了12名自闭症儿童和同等言语能力的28名正常儿童的表现,并分析了心理理论和中心信息整合的相关。结果表明:(1)中心信息整合的测量指标积木测验和镶嵌图形测验成绩保持中高度相关;(2)自闭症儿童中心信息整合显著弱于正常儿童;(3)心理理论和中心信息整合成绩相互独立。  相似文献   
596.
繁殖笼内川金丝猴社群结构的研究   总被引:6,自引:0,他引:6  
记录了繁殖笼内川金猴(Rhinopithecus roxellanae)成员之间发生的攻击和屈服行为的指向和次数,采用计算优势指数的方法,对数据进行统计和分析。通过优势指数的排列,以及与之有关事件的分析,结果表明繁殖笼内川金丝猴成员之间存在优势等级关系,但不是简单的线性排列;成员之间存在着有弹性的,有回旋余地的,复杂的社会网。  相似文献   
597.
恒河猴在繁殖笼内的等级结构   总被引:7,自引:0,他引:7  
有关非人灵长类社群结构的问题,国外已多有研究。许多学者认为无论在野外,或是在捕后(笼养)条件下进行观察都发现只要有几只动物在一起,形成一个群,那末群内的个体之间必然形成等级关系,而这种等级关系是线性排列的。换句话说,如果一群有A、B、C、D、E五只动物的话,它们的等级关系就是这样排列的:A>B>C>D>E。  相似文献   
598.
Two Minnesota Importance Questionnaire (MIQ) scales, Creativity and Independence were validated by experiment. Subjects were exposed to four task conditions representing joint combinations of high or low levels of Creativity and Independence. As a behavioral criterion of preference, subjects were then required to work for 12 sessions, each session under any (of the four) task condition of their choice. The behavioral results were consistent with the subjects' MIQ score levels on the two scales, thereby validating the scales.  相似文献   
599.
600.
梵二会议以天主爱他的受造物为出发点,抛弃了仅仅推崇天国而一味否定和贬低世俗世界、人和人的努力的传统立场,肯定了世界上的好的价值以及人的主观努力并赞美世界的进步和人的智慧的积极成果,指出真理的源头在天主,随着真理的发展,世界与天国互相渗透,最终合而为一。同时,梵二会议认为世界和人有或好或坏两种前途,因而必须求得教会的帮助归向天主。  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号