全文获取类型
收费全文 | 6657篇 |
免费 | 219篇 |
专业分类
6876篇 |
出版年
2021年 | 57篇 |
2020年 | 114篇 |
2019年 | 133篇 |
2018年 | 173篇 |
2017年 | 218篇 |
2016年 | 217篇 |
2015年 | 160篇 |
2014年 | 188篇 |
2013年 | 745篇 |
2012年 | 305篇 |
2011年 | 329篇 |
2010年 | 210篇 |
2009年 | 215篇 |
2008年 | 267篇 |
2007年 | 282篇 |
2006年 | 240篇 |
2005年 | 234篇 |
2004年 | 227篇 |
2003年 | 202篇 |
2002年 | 214篇 |
2001年 | 104篇 |
2000年 | 113篇 |
1999年 | 107篇 |
1998年 | 92篇 |
1997年 | 85篇 |
1996年 | 94篇 |
1995年 | 87篇 |
1994年 | 78篇 |
1993年 | 62篇 |
1992年 | 82篇 |
1991年 | 61篇 |
1990年 | 52篇 |
1989年 | 51篇 |
1988年 | 52篇 |
1987年 | 43篇 |
1986年 | 46篇 |
1985年 | 63篇 |
1984年 | 59篇 |
1983年 | 51篇 |
1982年 | 72篇 |
1981年 | 71篇 |
1980年 | 52篇 |
1979年 | 53篇 |
1978年 | 44篇 |
1977年 | 67篇 |
1976年 | 41篇 |
1975年 | 48篇 |
1974年 | 41篇 |
1973年 | 46篇 |
1972年 | 35篇 |
排序方式: 共有6876条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
251.
Raz, Shapiro, Fan, and Posner (2002) have recently provided a compelling demonstration of enhanced attentional control under post-hypnotic suggestion. Using the classic color-word interference paradigm, in which the task is to ignore a word and to name the color in which it is printed (e.g., RED in green, say "green"), they gave a post-hypnotic instruction to participants that they would be unable to read. This eliminated Stroop interference in high suggestibility participants but did not alter interference in low suggestibility participants. replicated this pattern and further demonstrated that it is not due to a visual strategy (such as blurring or looking at a different location). As a historical footnote, we describe a "case study" from 18 years ago in which we observed the same result using a hypnotic instruction to a single highly suggestible individual that he could not read. The elimination of Stroop interference has important implications for both the study of attention and the study of hypnosis. 相似文献
252.
Fishburn PC 《Journal of mathematical psychology》2001,45(1):53-80
Self-reflecting signed orders were proposed as an aid in estimating preference between subsets of items on the basis of limited information. The data of a signed order are preference comparisons that consider the desirability of excluding items from a subset as well as including items in a subset. This paper investigates signed orders within the setting of probabilistic choice and random utility theory. It focuses on linear signed order polytopes and their relationship to binary choice probabilities. The theory applies both to individual choice behavior and to group decision making. Copyright 2001 Academic Press. 相似文献
253.
According to the two-thirds power law the cube of the speed of a drawing movement is proportional to the radius of curvature of the trajectory, and the coefficient of proportionality has the meaning of mechanical power. We derive this empirical law from the variational principle known in physics as the principle of least action. It states that if a movement between two points of a given path obeys the two-thirds law, then the amount of work required to execute a trajectory in a fixed time is minimal. In this strict sense one may say that among infinitely many ways to execute a given path, the central nervous system chooses the most economical. We show that the kinematic equations for all drawing movements are solutions of a certain differential equation with a single (time-variable) coefficient. We consider several special cases of drawing movements corresponding to simplest forms of this coefficient. Copyright 2001 Academic Press. 相似文献
254.
255.
Paraconsistent logic is an area of philosophical logic that has yet to find acceptance from a wider audience. The area remains, in a word, disreputable. In this essay, we try to reassure potential consumers that it is not necessary to become a radical in order to use paraconsistent logic. According to the radicals, the problem is the absurd classical account of contradiction: Classically inconsistent sets explode only because bourgeois classical semantics holds, in the face of overwhelming evidence to the contrary, that both A and A cannot simultaneously be true! We suggest (more modestly) that there is, at least sometimes, something else worth preserving, even in an inconsistent, unsatisfiable premise set. In this paper we present, in a new guise, a very general version of this preservationist approach to paraconsistency. 相似文献
256.
Peter van Inwagen 《The Journal of Ethics》1999,3(4):343-351
In his classic paper, The Principle of Alternate Possibilities, Harry Frankfurt presented counterexamples to the principle named in his title: A person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise. He went on to argue that the falsity of the Principle of Alternate Possibilities (PAP) implied that the debate between the compatibilists and the incompatibilists (as regards determinism and the ability to do otherwise) did not have the significance that both parties had attributed to it -- since moral responsibility could exist even if no one was able to do otherwise. I have argued that even if PAP is false, there are other principles that imply that moral responsibility entails the ability to do otherwise, and that these principles are immune to Frankfurt-style counterexamples. Frankfurt has attempted to show that my arguments for this conclusion fail. This paper is a rejoinder to that reply; I argue that he has failed to show this. 相似文献
257.
Peter Marton 《The Philosophical quarterly》1999,49(194):72-77
The sceptic argues that we have little, if any, empirical knowledge. Recently Davidson offered a solution to this challenge by introducing his famous omniscient interpreter argument. Many of Davidson's critics claim that his solution is obviously flawed, since there is an unbridgeable gap between its premises. But I argue that even if his answer is formally acceptable, it is still problematic because circular. I focus on its modal character. Accordingly, a super-omniscient interpreter is introduced, who can beat Davidson's ordinary omniscient interpreter. This demonstrates that Davidson's semantic theory is not adequate for rebutting external-world scepticism; his argument is either circular or incorrigibly inconclusive. 相似文献
258.
Klein DN Lewinsohn PM Rohde P Seeley JR Durbin CE 《Journal of abnormal psychology》2002,111(1):98-106
Three questions were addressed using family study data from a community sample: (a) Which clinical features of major depressive disorder (MDD) in adolescents are associated with elevated rates of MDD in relatives? (b) Which features of MDD in relatives distinguish family members of depressed adolescents from relatives of adolescents without mood disorders (NMD)? and (c) Do depressed adolescents with particular features have higher proportions of depressed relatives with the same features? Participants included 268 MDD adolescents, 401 NMD adolescents, and their 2,202 first-degree relatives. Rates of MDD were highest among relatives of depressed adolescents with recurrent episodes and greater impairment. Depression severity best distinguished the relatives of depressed adolescents from relatives of controls. Specific clinical features did not aggregate in families. 相似文献
259.
Peter Ehlen 《Studies in East European Thought》1989,37(4):323-332
Ohne Zusammenfassung 相似文献
260.