首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   1032篇
  免费   37篇
  2022年   10篇
  2021年   8篇
  2020年   14篇
  2019年   14篇
  2018年   23篇
  2017年   22篇
  2016年   39篇
  2015年   19篇
  2014年   30篇
  2013年   126篇
  2012年   47篇
  2011年   57篇
  2010年   27篇
  2009年   23篇
  2008年   38篇
  2007年   29篇
  2006年   45篇
  2005年   27篇
  2004年   19篇
  2003年   30篇
  2002年   21篇
  2001年   15篇
  2000年   20篇
  1999年   12篇
  1998年   18篇
  1997年   14篇
  1996年   16篇
  1995年   15篇
  1994年   11篇
  1993年   17篇
  1992年   8篇
  1991年   16篇
  1990年   8篇
  1989年   15篇
  1986年   17篇
  1985年   15篇
  1984年   18篇
  1983年   16篇
  1982年   16篇
  1981年   15篇
  1980年   8篇
  1979年   9篇
  1978年   14篇
  1977年   6篇
  1975年   6篇
  1974年   13篇
  1973年   10篇
  1968年   7篇
  1967年   8篇
  1966年   8篇
排序方式: 共有1069条查询结果,搜索用时 281 毫秒
131.
132.
133.
This paper proposes that the psychological and behavioral effects of terrorist threat can be understood as a collective communication process that occurs between terrorists and their potential victims. Based on classic communication theory, terrorists are regarded as the senders of a specific collective message (such as ‘stop oppressing our culture’); a terrorist incident as the collective message itself (through its performance, modality and targets); and the potential victims as its collective receivers (who interpret the intention of the attack as a function of their pre-existing attributes, such as traits or salient social identities). The perception of terrorism as a dynamic and interactive process between collective senders, messages and receivers opens new theoretical perspectives regarding whether (a) terrorism can be successful in reaching its collective aim; (b) if it is interpreted as rational or irrational; and (c) how to counteract the vicious, cyclical relationship between terrorism and counter-terrorism. Previous findings on the psychology of terrorism can be organized within this theoretical framework, and the psychological impact of varying attributes of the perpetrators (senders), incident (message), and the reactions of the potential victims (receivers) systematically investigated. A series of self-conducted studies are also reviewed and found to provide direct support for the collective communication model of terrorism.  相似文献   
134.
135.
136.
ABSTRACT Scotus's belief that any created substance can depend on the divine essence and/or divine persons as a subject requires him to abandon the plausible Aristotelian principle that there is no merely relational change. I argue that Scotus's various counterexamples to the principle can be rebutted. For reasons related to those that arise in Scotus's failed attempt to refute the principle, the principle also entails that properties cannot be universals.  相似文献   
137.
138.
139.
The purpose of this research was to investigate a set of factors that may influence the perceived rate of an auditory event. In a paired-comparison task, subjects were presented with a set of music-like patterns that differed in their relative number of contour changes and in the magnitude of pitch skips (Experiment 1) as well as in the compatibility of rhythmic accent structure with the arrangement of pitch relations (Experiment 2). Results indicated that, relative to their standard referents, comparison melodies were judged to unfold more slowly when they displayed more changes in pitch direction, greater pitch distances, and an incompatible rhythmic accent structure. These findings are suggested to stern from animputed velocity hypo thesis, in which people overgeneralize certain invariant relations that typically occur between melodic and temporal accent structure within Western music.  相似文献   
140.
In The Philosophical Quarterly , 47 (1997), pp. 373–81, van Inwagen argues in a critical notice of my book The Metaphysics of Free Will that the impression that Frankfurt-type examples show that moral responsibility need not require alternative possibilities results from insufficient analytical precision. He suggests various precise principles which imply that moral responsibility requires alternative possibilities. In reply, I seek to defend the conclusion I have drawn from Frankfurt-type examples: moral responsibility need not require alternative possibilities. I contend that van Inwagen's principles — the principle of possible prevention and the no-matter-what principle — are invalid, and I suggest that their plausibility comes from thinking about a proper subset of the relevant cases.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号