全文获取类型
收费全文 | 67926篇 |
免费 | 2872篇 |
国内免费 | 28篇 |
专业分类
70826篇 |
出版年
2020年 | 813篇 |
2019年 | 922篇 |
2018年 | 1338篇 |
2017年 | 1323篇 |
2016年 | 1409篇 |
2015年 | 1028篇 |
2014年 | 1240篇 |
2013年 | 5723篇 |
2012年 | 2303篇 |
2011年 | 2264篇 |
2010年 | 1399篇 |
2009年 | 1402篇 |
2008年 | 1980篇 |
2007年 | 1955篇 |
2006年 | 1790篇 |
2005年 | 1526篇 |
2004年 | 1523篇 |
2003年 | 1448篇 |
2002年 | 1407篇 |
2001年 | 2357篇 |
2000年 | 2244篇 |
1999年 | 1661篇 |
1998年 | 761篇 |
1997年 | 663篇 |
1996年 | 731篇 |
1995年 | 650篇 |
1994年 | 652篇 |
1993年 | 624篇 |
1992年 | 1370篇 |
1991年 | 1276篇 |
1990年 | 1258篇 |
1989年 | 1184篇 |
1988年 | 1156篇 |
1987年 | 1080篇 |
1986年 | 1055篇 |
1985年 | 1095篇 |
1984年 | 928篇 |
1983年 | 793篇 |
1982年 | 610篇 |
1979年 | 945篇 |
1978年 | 699篇 |
1975年 | 762篇 |
1974年 | 870篇 |
1973年 | 891篇 |
1972年 | 755篇 |
1971年 | 716篇 |
1969年 | 627篇 |
1968年 | 787篇 |
1967年 | 677篇 |
1966年 | 641篇 |
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
31.
32.
Vladimir M. Sloutsky Yevgeniya Goldvarg 《The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A: Human Experimental Psychology》2004,57(4):636-665
Logical connectives, such as “AND”, “OR”, “IF . . . THEN”, and “IF AND ONLY IF” are ubiquitous in both language and cognition; however, reasoning with logical connectives is error-prone. We argue that some of these errors may stem from people's tendency to minimize the number of possibilities compatible with logical connectives and to construct a “minimalist” one-possibility representation. As a result, connectives denoting a single possibility (e.g., conjunctions) are likely to be represented correctly, whereas connectives denoting multiple possibilities (e.g., disjunctions or conditionals) are likely to be erroneously represented as conjunctions. These predictions were tested and confirmed in three experiments using different paradigms. In Experiment 1, participants were presented with a multiple-choice task and asked to select all and only those possibilities that would indicate that compound verbal propositions were true versus false. In Experiment 2, a somewhat similar task was used, except that participants were asked later to perform a cued recall of verbal propositions. Finally, Experiment 3 used an old/new recognition paradigm to examine participants' ability to accurately recognize different logical connectives. The results of the three experiments are discussed in relation to theories of representation of possibilities and theories of reasoning. 相似文献
33.
34.
The ability to make egocentric distance estimates of a single point source of light, seen in darkness and without the cues of changing size and luminance, was investigated in sixteen observers. The attenuation required to maintain constant luminance, when the target was viewed from different distances, was shown to follow the inverse square law providing the angle subtended by the light was less than 20 s arc. Distance changes were also simulated by means of a split mirror which produced vergence cues, or by test lenses to provide accommodation cues. Over the range 0.5 to 9.2 m distance estimates were surprisingly accurate, although there was some overestimation of near and underestimation of far distances. Most observers made good judgements when only convergence cues were varied, whereas no observers made consistently good judgements when only accommodation cues were varied. The difficulties are discussed in terms of the accommodation-convergence link. When distance was simulated by changing convergence and accommodation cues, estimates were not as good as when real distance was changed. Since good estimates were made with brief target exposures, these judgements were not based on subsequent convergence or accommodation changes. It is suggested that the metric or reference against which the apparently absolute judgements were made was the efferent demand signal associated with a 'resting' position of convergence in darkness. 相似文献
35.
36.
37.
38.
M. Victoria Costa 《Journal of applied philosophy》2004,21(1):1-14
abstract In Political Liberalism and later work John Rawls has recast his theory of justice as fairness in political terms. In order to illustrate the advantages of a liberal political approach to justice over liberal non‐political ones, Rawls discusses what kind of education might be required for future citizens of pluralistic and democratic societies. He advocates a rather minimal conception of civic education that he claims to derive from political liberalism. One group of authors has sided with Rawls’ political perspective and educational proposal, holding that a political approach and educational requirements that are not too demanding would have the advantage of being acceptable to a wide range of citizens with different religious, moral and philosophical perspectives. A second group of authors have criticized Rawls’ educational recommendations, holding that the production of a just society composed of reasonable citizens requires a more demanding civic education and, hence, that the political approach is not viable. The present paper argues that both groups are only partially right, and that there is a third way to understand civic education in Rawlsian terms, a way that is political but not minimal. 相似文献
39.
T. J. Roper R. A. Boakes 《The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section B: Comparative and Physiological Psychology》1981,33(2):137-140
TOATES, F. Animal Behaviour: A Systems Approach. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons. 1980. Pp. 299. Hardback £17. Paper back £6.40 ISBN 0 471 27724.
DICKINSON, A. Contemporary Animal Learning Theory. Cambridge: University Press. 1980. Pp. 177. Hardback £12.50. Paperback £3.95. ISBN 0 521 23469 7. 相似文献
DICKINSON, A. Contemporary Animal Learning Theory. Cambridge: University Press. 1980. Pp. 177. Hardback £12.50. Paperback £3.95. ISBN 0 521 23469 7. 相似文献
40.
Laura M. Hartman 《The Journal of religious ethics》2015,43(3):475-492
Despite this virtue's history as an instrument of women's oppression, modesty, at its most basic, means voluntary restraint of one's power, undertaken for the sake of others. It is a mechanism that modifies unequal power relationships and encourages greater compassion and fairness. I use a Christian perspective with influences from Jewish and Muslim sources to examine modesty. The modest person, I argue, must be in relationship with others, must be honestly aware of her impacts on others, must be sensitive to those impacts, compassionate toward others, and willing to hold back for others' sakes. Moreover, modesty is not only a virtue that pertains to sexuality and clothing, but it also can promote virtuous environmental behavior, particularly as it leads to awareness of, and sensitivity to, the effects of everyday behaviors on vulnerable others. 相似文献