首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   887篇
  免费   43篇
  2023年   6篇
  2020年   21篇
  2019年   21篇
  2018年   14篇
  2017年   24篇
  2016年   12篇
  2015年   18篇
  2014年   16篇
  2013年   106篇
  2012年   28篇
  2011年   35篇
  2010年   19篇
  2009年   22篇
  2008年   22篇
  2007年   30篇
  2006年   21篇
  2005年   25篇
  2004年   20篇
  2003年   33篇
  2002年   22篇
  2001年   18篇
  2000年   10篇
  1999年   10篇
  1998年   24篇
  1997年   8篇
  1996年   16篇
  1995年   6篇
  1994年   9篇
  1993年   11篇
  1992年   11篇
  1991年   7篇
  1990年   9篇
  1988年   8篇
  1987年   10篇
  1986年   9篇
  1985年   14篇
  1984年   7篇
  1983年   7篇
  1982年   12篇
  1981年   16篇
  1980年   14篇
  1979年   9篇
  1978年   13篇
  1977年   12篇
  1976年   19篇
  1974年   10篇
  1973年   10篇
  1971年   15篇
  1957年   5篇
  1955年   5篇
排序方式: 共有930条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
91.
A simple “expression” account of the relation between executive function (EF) and children's developing theory of mind (ToM) has difficulty accounting for the generality of the changes occurring in children's mental-state understanding during the preschool years. The current study of preschool children (N = 43) showed that EF—especially conflict EF—related uniformly to ToM measures that imposed either high or low executive demands, independent of verbal ability. These findings can be explained within an emergence account wherein executive skills are implicated in the acquisition of mental-state concepts as opposed to merely the expression of these concepts in task performance.  相似文献   
92.
In 1948 S. S. Stevens, in his famous Science article, proposed a theory of measurement that radically differed from the dominate theory of the time. The dominate theory held that all strong forms of scientific measurement— for example, those that yielded ratio scales—had to be based on an observable ordering and an observable commutative and associative operation. Stevens proposed different criteria and introduced his method of magnitude estimation. Stevens as well as measurement theorists considered his method to be radically different from those based on commutative and associative operations. Although his method was controversial, it became a standard tool in the behavioral sciences. This article argues that Stevens' method, together with implicit assumptions he made about the scales of measurement it generated, is from a mathematical perspective the same as the measurement process based on commutative and associative operations. The article also provides a theory of qualitative numbers and shows an interesting relationship between qualitative numbers and Stevens' method.  相似文献   
93.
Dempster ( Dempster, 1995 ; Dempster & Corkill, 1999 ) proposed that developmental changes in performance on Piagetian tasks could be related to changes in inhibitory efficiency more than to logical development. In this study, the negative priming paradigm was adapted to the class inclusion task in order to investigate the role of inhibition and knowledge levels in the development of class inclusion. Participants were pre‐tested on two inclusion tasks, the standard Piagetian task and Markman's modification task, and assigned to different knowledge levels: empirical, and logical necessity. Children were then tested on a priming version of the class inclusion task. Results showed a negative priming effect, indicating that the irrelevant ‘subclass comparison strategy’ was actively inhibited during the processing of the class inclusion task. This effect was found to vary as a function of knowledge levels, indicating that the need for inhibition was reduced when children had attained logical necessity.  相似文献   
94.
95.
Louis M. Guenin 《Synthese》2003,136(3):321-336
Two utilitarian defenses, traceable to Bentham and Mill, arecommonly offered for patents. It is contended that patents induce innovation, and thatpatents induce disclosure of innovation. Patents on some or all of the human genomepose particular challenges for these defenses. In the first instance, patents on nucleotidesequences entail the perverse notion of human reproduction qua infringement. In the second place, when such patents are available (as is presently the case), the two defenses involve a counterfactual claim, viz., that if there were no such patents, biotechnological progress would wane. Even if these challenges are met, concerns about respect for humanity generate opposition to property interests in compounds manipulated outside the human body but significantly homologous to compounds found in humans. This stance about things human might appear to commit the fallacy of division. In a dialogue between a Kantian and a utilitarian, arguments for and against property interests in the human genome are presented.  相似文献   
96.
97.
98.
99.
100.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号