全文获取类型
收费全文 | 20252篇 |
免费 | 412篇 |
国内免费 | 1篇 |
专业分类
20665篇 |
出版年
2020年 | 220篇 |
2019年 | 350篇 |
2018年 | 393篇 |
2017年 | 376篇 |
2016年 | 413篇 |
2015年 | 280篇 |
2014年 | 396篇 |
2013年 | 1751篇 |
2012年 | 619篇 |
2011年 | 685篇 |
2010年 | 414篇 |
2009年 | 452篇 |
2008年 | 602篇 |
2007年 | 572篇 |
2006年 | 562篇 |
2005年 | 471篇 |
2004年 | 499篇 |
2003年 | 455篇 |
2002年 | 439篇 |
2001年 | 493篇 |
2000年 | 557篇 |
1999年 | 368篇 |
1998年 | 245篇 |
1997年 | 193篇 |
1996年 | 199篇 |
1995年 | 186篇 |
1992年 | 302篇 |
1991年 | 303篇 |
1990年 | 317篇 |
1989年 | 295篇 |
1988年 | 286篇 |
1987年 | 259篇 |
1986年 | 273篇 |
1985年 | 282篇 |
1984年 | 223篇 |
1983年 | 238篇 |
1982年 | 181篇 |
1980年 | 182篇 |
1979年 | 269篇 |
1978年 | 235篇 |
1977年 | 172篇 |
1975年 | 222篇 |
1974年 | 254篇 |
1973年 | 274篇 |
1972年 | 231篇 |
1971年 | 216篇 |
1969年 | 200篇 |
1968年 | 254篇 |
1967年 | 243篇 |
1966年 | 210篇 |
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
231.
Previous research has shown that a task-irrelevant sudden onset of an object will capture an observer’s visual attention or draw it to that object (e.g., Yantis & Jonides, 1984). However, further research has demonstrated the apparent inability of an object with a task-irrelevant but unique color or luminance to capture attention (Jonides & Yantis, 1988). In the experiments reported here, we reexplore the question of whether task-irrelevant properties other than sudden onset may capture attention. Our results suggest that uniquely colored or luminous objects, as well as salient though irrelevant boundaries, do not appear to capture attention. However, these irrelevant features do appear to serve as landmarks for a top-down search strategy which becomes increasingly likely with larger display set sizes. These findings are described in terms of stimulus-driven and goal-directed aspects of attentional control. 相似文献
232.
233.
234.
Abstract: Do memories change as we acquire new information? Recent research on memory distortion using implicit tests along with research using confidence is reviewed and new studies are presented. Two new studies asked misinformed subjects to provide reasons for their answers. In each study 15% to 27% of subjects said they remembered seeing items they had only read about. In another study subjects were asked to identify the source of misleading items they had seen in slides or read in misleading questions. Subjects were more likely to say they had seen in slides something they read about in the questions than they were to confuse information from two nearly identical sets of slides. Recent work shows that, not only is it possible to distort memory for events, it is possible to implant an entire memory for something that never happened. The evidence is now clear that we can become mentally tricked into making large as well as small changes in the way we recall the past. 相似文献
235.
ITEM GENERATION PROCEDURES AND BACKGROUND DATA SCALES: IMPLICATIONS FOR CONSTRUCT AND CRITERION-RELATED VALIDITY 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
MICHAEL D. MUMFORD DAVID P. COSTANZA MARY SHANE CONNELLY JULIE F. JOHNSON 《Personnel Psychology》1996,49(2):361-398
Background data measures are one of the best predictors of job performance. Nonetheless, questions have been raised about their content and construct validity. The present effort describes a set of procedures for developing construct and content valid background data items. Data gathered in seven field studies and six laboratory studies are presented bearing on the reliability and validity of the measures constructed using these item generation procedures. Findings in these studies indicate that construct-based item generation procedures yield reliable scales evidencing both content and construct validity. Furthermore, these scales are capable of predicting performance in a variety of settings. Theoretical and practical implications of these findings for the development and validation of background data measures are discussed. 相似文献
236.
Cory F. Juhl 《Synthese》1996,109(3):293-309
Subjective Bayesians typically find the following objection difficult to answer: some joint probability measures lead to intuitively irrational inductive behavior, even in the long run. Yet well-motivated ways to restrict the set of reasonable prior joint measures have not been forthcoming. In this paper I propose a way to restrict the set of prior joint probability measures in particular inductive settings. My proposal is the following: where there exists some successful inductive method for getting to the truth in some situation, we ought to employ a (joint) probability measure that is inductively successful in that situation, if such a measure exists. In order to do show that the restriction is possible to meet in a broad class of cases, I prove a Bayesian Completeness Theorem, which says that for any solvable inductive problem of a certain broad type, there exist probability measures that a Bayesian could use to solve the problem. I then briefly compare the merits of my proposal with two other well-known proposals for constraining the class of admissible subjective probability measures, the leave the door ajar condition and the maximize entropy condition.The author owes special thanks to Kevin Kelly, for a number of helpful ideas for the proof of the Bayesian Completeness Theorem, as well as other aspects of the paper. Thanks also to Clark Glymour for some helpful suggestions for improvement of an earlier draft. Part of the work leading to this paper was funded by a Summer Research Grant from the University Research Institute of the University of Texas at Austin. 相似文献
237.
John F. Horty 《Synthese》1996,108(2):269-307
The purpose of this paper is to explore a new deontic operator for representing what an agent ought to do; the operator is cast against the background of a modal treatment of action developed by Nuel Belnap and Michael Perloff, which itself relies on Arthur Prior's indeterministic tense logic. The analysis developed here of what an agent ought to do is based on a dominance ordering adapted from the decision theoretic study of choice under uncertainty to the present account of action. It is shown that this analysis gives rise to a normal deontic operator, and that the result is superior to an analysis that identifies what an agent ought to do with what it ought to be that the agent does. 相似文献
238.
239.
Meredith Child Kathryn Graff Low Cheryl McDonell McCormick Andrew Cocciarella 《Sex roles》1996,34(5-6):447-455
Transsexuals, because of their attempts at gender reversal, offer a unique opportunity to study self-presentation, social roles, and stereotypes. The present study is a content analysis of personal advertisements of male-to-female transsexuals (TM, N =99), homosexual (HoM, N =64) and heterosexual men (HM, N =99), and heterosexual women (HW, N =99). Advertisements were coded for the presence or absence of 11 characteristics either offered or sought, based on the 1984 work of Deaux and Hanna. The content of TM personal advertisements was significantly different from those of HW, HM, or HoM. TM mentioned physical characteristics and sincerity, and requested friendship most often; HoM mentioned sexuality most often; HM offered financial security and status in the form of occupation, and listed marital status most often; and HW offered personality characteristics and attractiveness most often. Several factors may contribute to the pattern of differences observed, including the fact that TM were more likely to be seeking friendship than sexual partners, in contrast to the other three groups. 相似文献
240.
J. F. Dmonet J. A. Fiez E. Paulesu S. E. Petersen R. J. Zatorre 《Brain and language》1996,55(3):352-379
Poeppel (1996) raises a number of criticisms about the methods and reported results for eight studies of phonological processing from six different neuroimaging laboratories. We would freely admit that valid criticisms of PET methodology can be made and that, like any method, it has limitations; in fact, we and others have engaged in such critical commentary (Steinmetz & Seitz, 1991; Sergent et al., 1992; Démonet, 1995; Fiez et al., 1996a; Zatorre et al., 1996). Poeppel's analysis, though, falls far short of providing new insights into the limitations of PET methodology or the means by which future functional imaging studies could be improved. Many of Poeppel's criticisms derive from a failure to understand some of the fundamental issues which motivate functional imaging studies, including those he reviews. However, we are grateful to our critic inasmuch as he offers us the challenge to clarify our positions on important aspects of our experimental design, analysis, and interpretation. In our discussion of these issues, we begin with a general commentary, followed by specific comments from individual authors. 相似文献