首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   475篇
  免费   10篇
  国内免费   1篇
  2020年   6篇
  2019年   4篇
  2018年   5篇
  2017年   8篇
  2016年   11篇
  2015年   6篇
  2014年   16篇
  2013年   41篇
  2012年   11篇
  2011年   14篇
  2010年   14篇
  2009年   14篇
  2008年   15篇
  2007年   14篇
  2006年   19篇
  2005年   15篇
  2004年   16篇
  2003年   15篇
  2002年   10篇
  2001年   6篇
  2000年   6篇
  1999年   6篇
  1998年   7篇
  1997年   6篇
  1996年   5篇
  1995年   5篇
  1994年   8篇
  1993年   13篇
  1992年   13篇
  1991年   8篇
  1990年   10篇
  1989年   6篇
  1987年   7篇
  1986年   6篇
  1985年   6篇
  1982年   4篇
  1981年   4篇
  1979年   7篇
  1978年   5篇
  1977年   4篇
  1975年   9篇
  1974年   5篇
  1973年   7篇
  1972年   10篇
  1971年   5篇
  1968年   7篇
  1967年   5篇
  1959年   3篇
  1953年   3篇
  1937年   3篇
排序方式: 共有486条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
211.
212.
Frankel's paper is related to issues in the study of multiple personality, as well as to the dilemmas of identification in psychoanalytic training. The main point raised in this discussion is that the generalization that all identification is related to fear is untenable and that a continuum should be recognized between identification with the other in a close relationship as a constructive building block of one's identity and a traumatic identification with the aggressor that results in alienation.  相似文献   
213.
This study investigated the kinds of knowledge necessary to learn an important troubleshooting strategy, elimination. A total of 50 college-level students searched for the source of failures in simple digital networks. Production system modelling suggested that students using a common but simpler backtracking strategy would learn the more advanced elimination strategy if they applied certain domain-specific knowledge and the general-purpose problem-solving strategy of reductio ad absurdum. In an experiment, students solved network troubleshooting problems after being trained with either the domain-specific knowledge, the reductio ad absurdum strategy, both types of knowledge, or neither. Students needed both the domain-specific and general knowledge identified by the models in order to significantly increase their elimination use.  相似文献   
214.
215.
216.
217.
People across the world seek out beautiful sounds in nature, such as a babbling brook or a nightingale song, for positive human experiences. However, it is unclear whether this positive aesthetic response is driven by a preference for the perceptual features typical of nature sounds versus a higher‐order association of nature with beauty. To test these hypotheses, participants provided aesthetic judgments for nature and urban soundscapes that varied on ease of recognition. Results demonstrated that the aesthetic preference for nature soundscapes was eliminated for the sounds hardest to recognize, and moreover the relationship between aesthetic ratings and several measured acoustic features significantly changed as a function of recognition. In a follow‐up experiment, requiring participants to classify these difficult‐to‐identify sounds into nature or urban categories resulted in a robust preference for nature sounds and a relationship between aesthetic ratings and our measured acoustic features that was more typical of easy‐to‐identify sounds. This pattern of results was replicated with computer‐generated artificial noises, which acoustically shared properties with the nature and urban soundscapes but by definition did not come from these environments. Taken together, these results support the conclusion that the recognition of a sound as either natural or urban dynamically organizes the relationship between aesthetic preference and perceptual features and that these preferences are not inherent to the acoustic features. Implications for nature's role in cognitive and affective restoration are discussed.  相似文献   
218.
219.
220.
In Beyond Rigidity, Soames attempts to defend Millianism by articulating a novel account of the semantics and pragmatics of sentences containing names. Soames uses this account both to respond to the objection that Millianism unintuitively allows the unrestricted substitution of coreferential names in propositional attitude contexts, and to generate a positive argument for Millianism. I argue that the positive argument fails, and that Soames’s account of the semantics and pragmatics of sentences containing names is inconsistent with Millianism.
Leo IaconoEmail:
  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号