首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   650篇
  免费   33篇
  2022年   7篇
  2021年   7篇
  2020年   10篇
  2019年   9篇
  2018年   16篇
  2017年   19篇
  2016年   24篇
  2015年   17篇
  2014年   15篇
  2013年   74篇
  2012年   20篇
  2011年   21篇
  2010年   18篇
  2009年   20篇
  2008年   28篇
  2007年   31篇
  2006年   24篇
  2005年   16篇
  2004年   22篇
  2003年   17篇
  2002年   20篇
  2001年   13篇
  2000年   17篇
  1999年   10篇
  1998年   9篇
  1997年   4篇
  1995年   5篇
  1994年   7篇
  1993年   5篇
  1992年   13篇
  1991年   10篇
  1990年   10篇
  1989年   7篇
  1988年   9篇
  1987年   9篇
  1986年   14篇
  1985年   5篇
  1984年   13篇
  1983年   9篇
  1982年   5篇
  1981年   8篇
  1980年   3篇
  1979年   4篇
  1978年   4篇
  1977年   4篇
  1976年   7篇
  1975年   9篇
  1974年   6篇
  1971年   4篇
  1968年   4篇
排序方式: 共有683条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
141.
142.
143.
144.
The arguments for and against Puccetti’s (1981a) notion of “mental duality” are reviewed. This model of mind asserts that not only do commissurotomy patients have two independent spheres of consciousness but so do normal intact brains. The role of the corpus callosum is viewed as being purely duplicative, not integrative. Following a detailed discussion of conceptual and terminological issues, neuropsychological and neuroanatomical considerations, and various clinical implications of the model, it is concluded that the available empirical evidence refutes the model and that the model is conceptually inadequate.  相似文献   
145.
The arguments for and against Puccetti’s (1981a) notion of “mental duality” are reviewed. This model of mind asserts that not only do commissurotomy patients have two independent spheres of consciousness but so do normal intact brains. The role of the corpus callosum is viewed as being purely duplicative, not integrative. Following a detailed discussion of conceptual and terminological issues, neuropsychological and neuroanatomical considerations, and various clinical implications of the model, it is concluded that the available empirical evidence refutes the model and that the model is conceptually inadequate.  相似文献   
146.
The original hypothesis of Dixon, Brunet, and Laurence (1990) that highly hypnotizable (HH) subjects process words more automatically than do low hypnotizable (LH) subjects was retested in a paradigm that separated strategic from automatic processes in the Stroop color-naming task. The words red and blue preceded a color patch that was red or blue. Subjects were told that the word predicted the opposite color 75% of the time. Automatic and strategic processes were assessed by varying the interstimulus interval (ISI) between the word and the color patch. Both HH and LH subjects showed significant strategic effects (faster incongruent-trial, color-naming reaction times than congruent-trial reaction times at ISIs over 400 ms), but only HH subjects showed significant automaticity (significantly faster congruent-trial reaction times than incongruent-trial reaction times at 16.7 ms, the lowest ISI).  相似文献   
147.
We report the results of 2 studies on food-elicited vocalizations in golden lion tamarins (Leontopithecus rosalia). First, we investigated the preferences of 10 golden lion tamarins for 6 foods. Tamarins prefer mealworms and raisins significantly more than apple, egg, carrot, or marmoset diet. Food preference rank was significantly and positively correlated with the rank of latency to choose a particular food. Second, we investigated the relation between food preference and 15 vocal parameters measured from the calls emitted by 5 tamarins to a subset of the foods. Only 1 parameter was significantly correlated with food preference across animals. Within-subjects multivariate analysis of variance showed that the vocalizations to foods are significantly different. Our results support an hypothesis that food-elicited vocalizations vary in ways that correspond to the caller's preference but not in a manner that labels food type.  相似文献   
148.
Those of us who work in the field of bioethics tend to think that, because the word "bioethics" is new, so too the field is new in all respects, but we are not the first to do bioethics. John Gregory (1724-1773) did bioethics just as we do it, at least two centuries before we thought to do it. He deployed philosophical methods as sophisticated as our own. Indeed, Gregory took up the very best moral philosophy available to thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment, namely, David Hume's moral philosophy and its core concept of sympathy. Gregory also responded in a conceptually powerful and clinically applicable way to the problems of his time, just as we do. I want here to outline Gregory's accomplishment and to identify some aspects of its importance for bioethics in the twenty-first century.  相似文献   
149.
150.
Assigned participants in the Hypertension Prevention Trial to one of four diets for a period of 3 years: (a) weight loss, (b) reduced sodium, (c) weight loss plus reduced sodium, and (d) reduced sodium plus increased potassium. At 6-month intervals, they reported problems they were having adhering to their diets. Problem attributions were coded along the dimensions of internality, stability, and controllability and were categorized as intrapersonal or extrapersonal. Attributions were found to differ by type of diet and sex of participant. Participants assigned to weight-loss groups were significantly more likely than those assigned to non-weight-loss groups to blame themselves for their problems with adherence, making characterological as opposed to external or situational attributions. Men perceived problems to be more controllable than women. Attributions did not predict weight loss, change in urinary sodium, or change in potassium excretion.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号