全文获取类型
收费全文 | 727篇 |
免费 | 9篇 |
专业分类
736篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 4篇 |
2023年 | 7篇 |
2022年 | 5篇 |
2021年 | 6篇 |
2020年 | 14篇 |
2019年 | 18篇 |
2018年 | 12篇 |
2017年 | 20篇 |
2016年 | 26篇 |
2015年 | 14篇 |
2014年 | 29篇 |
2013年 | 87篇 |
2012年 | 34篇 |
2011年 | 40篇 |
2010年 | 25篇 |
2009年 | 27篇 |
2008年 | 28篇 |
2007年 | 29篇 |
2006年 | 33篇 |
2005年 | 27篇 |
2004年 | 27篇 |
2003年 | 27篇 |
2002年 | 24篇 |
2001年 | 9篇 |
2000年 | 10篇 |
1999年 | 7篇 |
1998年 | 15篇 |
1997年 | 12篇 |
1996年 | 5篇 |
1995年 | 10篇 |
1994年 | 9篇 |
1993年 | 4篇 |
1992年 | 6篇 |
1990年 | 4篇 |
1989年 | 3篇 |
1988年 | 7篇 |
1987年 | 4篇 |
1984年 | 5篇 |
1983年 | 5篇 |
1982年 | 6篇 |
1981年 | 5篇 |
1980年 | 3篇 |
1979年 | 4篇 |
1978年 | 4篇 |
1977年 | 5篇 |
1976年 | 3篇 |
1974年 | 7篇 |
1971年 | 3篇 |
1970年 | 3篇 |
1968年 | 2篇 |
排序方式: 共有736条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
641.
642.
Jon Elster 《Synthese》2016,193(7):2159-2184
643.
644.
645.
Jon Robson 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2018,96(4):657-668
It is commonplace amongst philosophers of art to make claims that postulate important links between aesthetics and perception. In this paper, I focus on one such claim—that perception is the canonical route to aesthetic judgment. I consider a range of prima facie plausible interpretations of this claim, and argue that each fails to identify any important link between aesthetic judgment and perception. Given this, I conclude that we have good reason to be sceptical of the claim that perception is in any way privileged as a source of aesthetic judgment. 相似文献
646.
When people are asked to report their beliefs in a (target) statement, they may search memory for other, “informational” propositions that bear on its validity, and may use their beliefs in these propositions as bases for their judgments. Several factors were hypothesized to affect the particular propositions that subjects are likely to recall under such conditions. Subjects first familiarized themselves with a list of informational and target propositions. Then, they reported either their beliefs in these propositions or their attitudes toward them. In a second session 1 week later, they recalled as many of the propositions as they could. Both informational and target statements were better recalled when the informational propositions were unlikely to be true. In addition, the target statements were better recalled when the informational propositions associated with them had unclear implications for their validity. Recall of one proposition was more likely to cue the recall of the other when subjects had previously reported belief in the target proposition (rather than attitudes toward it). However, it was more likely to occur when subjects had reported attitudes toward the informational proposition (rather than beliefs in it). The effects of these variables were interpreted in terms of their mediating influence on the strength of association between the informational proposition and both (a) the target proposition and (b) contextual and environmental cues in the situation where target beliefs are reported. 相似文献
647.
648.
649.
650.