首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   103004篇
  免费   4248篇
  国内免费   38篇
  107290篇
  2020年   1107篇
  2019年   1369篇
  2018年   1897篇
  2017年   1960篇
  2016年   2061篇
  2015年   1483篇
  2014年   1764篇
  2013年   8371篇
  2012年   3292篇
  2011年   3416篇
  2010年   2107篇
  2009年   2125篇
  2008年   2983篇
  2007年   2988篇
  2006年   2741篇
  2005年   2379篇
  2004年   2290篇
  2003年   2179篇
  2002年   2218篇
  2001年   3295篇
  2000年   3154篇
  1999年   2385篇
  1998年   1179篇
  1997年   1048篇
  1996年   1082篇
  1995年   988篇
  1993年   970篇
  1992年   2000篇
  1991年   1875篇
  1990年   1888篇
  1989年   1734篇
  1988年   1689篇
  1987年   1608篇
  1986年   1650篇
  1985年   1706篇
  1984年   1445篇
  1983年   1291篇
  1981年   947篇
  1979年   1520篇
  1978年   1113篇
  1975年   1222篇
  1974年   1358篇
  1973年   1466篇
  1972年   1218篇
  1971年   1146篇
  1970年   1023篇
  1969年   1041篇
  1968年   1306篇
  1967年   1176篇
  1966年   1059篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
41.
Do the conditions under which promises are made determine whether they ought to be kept? Philosophers have placed a number of conditions on promising which, they hold, must be met in order to make promise-keeping obligatory. In so doing, they have distinguished valid promises from invalid promises and justified promises from promises that are not justified. Considering such conditions, one by one, we argue that they are mistaken. In the first place, the conditions they lay down are not necessary for either valid or justified promise-making. In the second place, promises need not meet such conditions in order to create moral obligations. In general, such analyses of promising fail because they suffer from a confusion between promise-making and promise-keeping. Philosophers have wrongly supposed that obligations to keep promises are dependent upon, or derivable from, the quality of the promises themselves, at the time they are made, instead of focusing on conditions that must be satisfied at the time when promises are supposed to be kept. It is not the quality of a promise that determines an obligation to keep it but the rightness or wrongness of performing the promised act.  相似文献   
42.
43.
44.
Are different responses differentially associable with their consequences? An overshadowing design was used to try to answer this question for three responses previously studied in golden hamsters. In Experiment I, scrabbling was rapidly suppressed by electric shock punishment, and it overshadowed a tone which occurred between scrabbling and shock. In Experiment II, no evidence of response-shock association was obtained when open rearing was the punished response, and open rearing did not overshadow the tone. Punishment had some effect on face washing, but there was no statistically significant overshadowing with this response. These results are consistent with the idea that differences in punishment suppression among these three responses have an associative basis. They also demonstrate the usefulness of a novel paradigm for studying “preparedness” of response-reinforcer associations.  相似文献   
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
Logical connectives, such as “AND”, “OR”, “IF . . . THEN”, and “IF AND ONLY IF” are ubiquitous in both language and cognition; however, reasoning with logical connectives is error-prone. We argue that some of these errors may stem from people's tendency to minimize the number of possibilities compatible with logical connectives and to construct a “minimalist” one-possibility representation. As a result, connectives denoting a single possibility (e.g., conjunctions) are likely to be represented correctly, whereas connectives denoting multiple possibilities (e.g., disjunctions or conditionals) are likely to be erroneously represented as conjunctions. These predictions were tested and confirmed in three experiments using different paradigms. In Experiment 1, participants were presented with a multiple-choice task and asked to select all and only those possibilities that would indicate that compound verbal propositions were true versus false. In Experiment 2, a somewhat similar task was used, except that participants were asked later to perform a cued recall of verbal propositions. Finally, Experiment 3 used an old/new recognition paradigm to examine participants' ability to accurately recognize different logical connectives. The results of the three experiments are discussed in relation to theories of representation of possibilities and theories of reasoning.  相似文献   
50.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号