首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   173120篇
  免费   7800篇
  国内免费   156篇
  181076篇
  2021年   1484篇
  2020年   2758篇
  2019年   3418篇
  2018年   3505篇
  2017年   3952篇
  2016年   4591篇
  2015年   3903篇
  2014年   4779篇
  2013年   23367篇
  2012年   4545篇
  2011年   3689篇
  2010年   3864篇
  2009年   4743篇
  2008年   3841篇
  2007年   3423篇
  2006年   4053篇
  2005年   4011篇
  2004年   3524篇
  2003年   3130篇
  2002年   2974篇
  2001年   3266篇
  2000年   3074篇
  1999年   3091篇
  1998年   2817篇
  1997年   2649篇
  1996年   2572篇
  1995年   2404篇
  1994年   2375篇
  1993年   2323篇
  1992年   2552篇
  1991年   2396篇
  1990年   2252篇
  1989年   2209篇
  1988年   2176篇
  1987年   2204篇
  1986年   2169篇
  1985年   2425篇
  1984年   2516篇
  1983年   2319篇
  1982年   2372篇
  1981年   2341篇
  1980年   2184篇
  1979年   2207篇
  1978年   2180篇
  1977年   2134篇
  1976年   1953篇
  1975年   1999篇
  1974年   2045篇
  1973年   1954篇
  1972年   1529篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
121.
Intention is theorized as the proximal determinant of behavior in some theories of motivation, but the need to understand predictors of action control (i.e., translating an intention into behavior) is warranted to tailor physical activity intervention efforts. The purpose of this study was to examine constructs of the transtheoretical model of behavior change (TTM) as predictors of physical activity intention-behavior profiles across 6 months in a large Canadian sample (N = 1,192). Results showed that 5 of the 8 possible intention-behavior profiles had a substantial number of participants: nonintenders, unsuccessful adopters, successful adopters, unsuccessful maintainers, and successful maintainers. Constructs of the TTM distinguished (p < .01) intention-behavior profiles. Self-efficacy and the behavioral processes of change were particularly good predictors of action control (p < .01), but disaggregated beliefs and processes identified specific intervention targets for successful physical activity adoption and maintenance. The results validate that both action planning and action control are important when understanding physical activity behavior.  相似文献   
122.
123.
124.
125.
Two experiments examined repetition priming in the recognition of famous voices. In Experiment 1, reaction times for fame decisions to famous voice samples were shorter than in an unprimed condition, when voices were primed by a different voice sample of the same person having been presented in an earlier phase of the experiment. No effect of voice repetition was observed for non-famous voices. In Experiment 2, it was investigated whether this priming effect is voice-specific or whether it is related to post-perceptual processes in person recognition. Recognizing a famous voice was again primed by having earlier heard a different voice sample of that person. Although an earlier exposure to that person's name did not cause any priming, there was some indication of priming following an earlier exposure to that person's face. Finally, earlier exposure to the identical voice sample (as compared to a different voice sample from the same person) caused a considerable bias towards responding 'famous'-i.e. performance benefits for famous but costs for nonfamous voices. The findings suggestthat (1) repetition priming invoice recognition primarily involves the activation of perceptual representations of voices, and (2) it is important to determine the conditions in which priming causes bias effects that need to be disentangled from performance benefits.  相似文献   
126.
127.
128.
129.
130.
Do the conditions under which promises are made determine whether they ought to be kept? Philosophers have placed a number of conditions on promising which, they hold, must be met in order to make promise-keeping obligatory. In so doing, they have distinguished valid promises from invalid promises and justified promises from promises that are not justified. Considering such conditions, one by one, we argue that they are mistaken. In the first place, the conditions they lay down are not necessary for either valid or justified promise-making. In the second place, promises need not meet such conditions in order to create moral obligations. In general, such analyses of promising fail because they suffer from a confusion between promise-making and promise-keeping. Philosophers have wrongly supposed that obligations to keep promises are dependent upon, or derivable from, the quality of the promises themselves, at the time they are made, instead of focusing on conditions that must be satisfied at the time when promises are supposed to be kept. It is not the quality of a promise that determines an obligation to keep it but the rightness or wrongness of performing the promised act.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号