首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   1579篇
  免费   62篇
  国内免费   5篇
  2021年   15篇
  2020年   20篇
  2019年   18篇
  2018年   36篇
  2017年   32篇
  2016年   41篇
  2015年   24篇
  2014年   37篇
  2013年   183篇
  2012年   53篇
  2011年   63篇
  2010年   36篇
  2009年   54篇
  2008年   51篇
  2007年   61篇
  2006年   60篇
  2005年   54篇
  2004年   42篇
  2003年   43篇
  2002年   39篇
  2001年   21篇
  2000年   22篇
  1999年   20篇
  1998年   34篇
  1997年   16篇
  1996年   18篇
  1995年   22篇
  1994年   17篇
  1993年   16篇
  1992年   23篇
  1991年   17篇
  1990年   14篇
  1989年   19篇
  1988年   16篇
  1987年   15篇
  1985年   19篇
  1984年   18篇
  1983年   14篇
  1981年   19篇
  1980年   19篇
  1979年   15篇
  1978年   20篇
  1977年   17篇
  1976年   21篇
  1975年   16篇
  1974年   17篇
  1972年   16篇
  1968年   17篇
  1967年   17篇
  1966年   19篇
排序方式: 共有1646条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
201.
202.
For people to contribute to discourse, they must do more than utter the right sentence at the right time. The basic requirement is that they add to their common ground in an orderly way. To do this, we argue, they try to establish for each utterance the mutual belief that the addressees have understood what the speaker meant well enough for current purposes. This is accomplished by the collective actions of the current contributor and his or her partners, and these result in units of conversation called contributions. We present a model of contributions and show how it accounts for a variety of features of everyday conversations.  相似文献   
203.
204.
205.
206.
207.
208.
Bradley  Richard 《Synthese》1998,116(2):187-229
This paper investigates the role of conditionals in hypothetical reasoning and rational decision making. Its main result is a proof of a representation theorem for preferences defined on sets of sentences (and, in particular, conditional sentences), where an agent’s preference for one sentence over another is understood to be a preference for receiving the news conveyed by the former. The theorem shows that a rational preference ordering of conditional sentences determines probability and desirability representations of the agent’s degrees of belief and desire that satisfy, in the case of non-conditional sentences, the axioms of Jeffrey’s decision theory and, in the case of conditional sentences, Adams’ expression for the probabilities of conditionals. Furthermore, the probability representation is shown to be unique and the desirability representation unique up to positive linear transformation. This revised version was published online in June 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date.  相似文献   
209.
This outline of the transformations of the concept of reason is based on the idea that this can be presented/illustrated by means of a historical sketch of the criticism of reason, because all essential differentiations in that concept can be understood as consequences of critical arguments. In Kant's work, the Critique of Speculative Reason reaches its first conclusion; it was followed by a Critique of Critical Reason by Hegel and his followers, and Schopenhauer established a new type of critical argument: the Critique of Functional Reason which dominates the radical criticism of reason in our time. This radical criticism is the great challenge for the philosophy of reason today.  相似文献   
210.
We show that if overall sample size and effect size are held constant, the power of theF test for a one-way analysis of variance decreases dramatically as the number of groups increases. This reduction in power is even greater when the groups added to the design do not produce treatment effects. If a second independent variable is added to the design, either a split-plot or a completely randomized design may be employed. For the split-plot design, we show that the power of theF test on the betweengroups factor decreases as the correlation across the levels of the within-groups factor increases. The attenuation in between-groups power becomes more pronounced as the number of levels of the withingroups factor increases. Sample size and total cost calculations are required to determine whether the split-plot or completely randomized design is more efficient in a particular application. The outcome hinges on the cost of obtaining (or recruiting) a single subject relative to the cost of obtaining a single observation: We call this thesubject-to-observation cost (SOC) ratio. Split-plot designs are less costly than completely randomized designs only when the SOC ratio is high, the correlation across the levels of the within-groups factor is low, and the number of such levels is small.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号