首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   91篇
  免费   2篇
  2023年   2篇
  2017年   1篇
  2016年   2篇
  2015年   2篇
  2014年   1篇
  2013年   6篇
  2012年   2篇
  2011年   1篇
  2010年   3篇
  2009年   1篇
  2008年   2篇
  2007年   2篇
  2006年   2篇
  2005年   1篇
  2004年   1篇
  2003年   5篇
  2002年   1篇
  2001年   2篇
  2000年   4篇
  1999年   1篇
  1998年   4篇
  1997年   1篇
  1996年   2篇
  1994年   4篇
  1993年   1篇
  1992年   1篇
  1991年   1篇
  1990年   4篇
  1988年   2篇
  1987年   1篇
  1986年   1篇
  1984年   1篇
  1983年   1篇
  1981年   1篇
  1980年   2篇
  1979年   2篇
  1978年   2篇
  1977年   2篇
  1976年   1篇
  1975年   1篇
  1974年   3篇
  1973年   1篇
  1972年   2篇
  1971年   2篇
  1970年   1篇
  1968年   1篇
  1967年   1篇
  1966年   1篇
  1965年   2篇
  1926年   1篇
排序方式: 共有93条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
11.
12.
Children with a history of child maltreatment often have limited social interactions with other children and adults. This study examined the effects of a Peer Engagement Program, consisting of peer mentoring and social skills training with positive reinforcement, in three children with low levels of oral and social interaction. A multiple baseline, single-subject research design was used to test whether introduction of the intervention was associated with increased, directly observed oral interaction and engagement in social activities with peers and adults. The Child Behavior Checklist (CBCL) and the Social Skills Rating Scale (SSRS) were administered before and after intervention. All children showed increased levels of oral and social interaction and improved scores on the SSRS and the CBCL.  相似文献   
13.
14.
Filing charges of scientific misconduct can be a risky and dangerous endeavor. This article presents rules of conduct to follow when considering whether to report perceived misconduct, and a set of step-by-step procedures for responsible whistleblowing that describe how to do so once the decision to report misconduct has been made. This advice is framed within the university setting, and may not apply fully in industrial settings. Ms. Gunsalus, an attorney, has been responsible for a wide range of compliance issues and academic policy matters at her university including responding to allegations of scientific misconduct. She served on the United States Commission on Research Integrity and spent six years on the AAAS Committee on Scientific Freedom and Responsibility, four of them as chair. An earlier version of this paper was presented at the symposium entitled “Damned If You Do, Damned If You Don’t: What the Scientific Community Can Do About Whistleblowing” held during the Annual Meeting of the AAAS, Seattle, Washington, 15 February, 1997.  相似文献   
15.
16.
17.
18.
Jerry Fodor  & Ernie Lepore 《Ratio》2001,14(4):350-368
Paul Horwich argues for a 'deflationary'account of compositionality, according to which, '. . . the compositionality of meaning imposes no constraint at all on how the meaning properties of words are constituted'. We have arrived at a tentative diagnosis, which is that Horwich fails to enforce several distinctions that turn out to be crucial. For example, sometimes he puts his main conclusion in the way we just quoted but sometimes, even on the following page, he puts it like this: 'understanding one of oneÕs own complex expressions (non-idiomatically) is, by definition, nothing over and above understanding its parts and knowing how they are combined'. We propose, in what follows, to consider how Horwich's deflationary account of compositionality fares if the distinction between theories of meaning and theories of understanding is properly attended to. Here's how we think it all turns out:
– Horwich is right to claim that compositionality is neutral with respect to the metaphysics of understanding expressions when 'understanding' refers to a (merely) dispositional state; but not when it refers to an occurrent state.
– Horwich is right strictu dictu to claim that compositionality is neutral with respect to the character of lexical meanings, but only strictu dictu.
– Compositionality taken, together with other constraints that semantic theories are required to satisfy, reduces the options in the theory of lexical meaning to a bare minimum.
The first part of the paper is about compositionality and understanding, the second part is about compositionality and lexical meaning.  相似文献   
19.
A theory of the child's theory of mind.   总被引:11,自引:0,他引:11  
J A Fodor 《Cognition》1992,44(3):283-296
  相似文献   
20.
J Fodor  B P McLaughlin 《Cognition》1990,35(2):183-204
In two recent papers, Paul Smolensky responds to a challenge Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn posed for connectionist theories of cognition: to explain the existence of systematic relations among cognitive capacities without assuming that mental processes are causally sensitive to the constituent structure of mental representations. Smolensky thinks connectionists can explain systematicity if they avail themselves of "distributed" mental representation. In facts, Smolensky offers two accounts of distributed mental representation, corresponding to his notions of "weak" and "strong" compositional structure. We argue that weak compositional structure is irrelevant to the systematicity problem and of dubious internal coherence. We then argue that strong compositional (tensor product) representations fail to explain systematicity because they fail to exhibit the sort of constituents that can provide domains for structure sensitive mental processes.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号