首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   314篇
  免费   11篇
  2021年   2篇
  2020年   4篇
  2019年   12篇
  2018年   8篇
  2017年   9篇
  2016年   6篇
  2015年   6篇
  2014年   3篇
  2013年   39篇
  2012年   16篇
  2011年   15篇
  2010年   7篇
  2009年   5篇
  2008年   8篇
  2007年   18篇
  2006年   12篇
  2005年   5篇
  2004年   10篇
  2003年   10篇
  2002年   10篇
  2001年   4篇
  2000年   2篇
  1999年   2篇
  1998年   3篇
  1995年   3篇
  1994年   4篇
  1993年   6篇
  1991年   3篇
  1990年   4篇
  1988年   5篇
  1987年   5篇
  1986年   4篇
  1985年   3篇
  1984年   4篇
  1982年   4篇
  1981年   3篇
  1980年   4篇
  1979年   4篇
  1978年   3篇
  1977年   6篇
  1976年   2篇
  1975年   2篇
  1973年   3篇
  1972年   4篇
  1970年   5篇
  1969年   3篇
  1968年   2篇
  1967年   6篇
  1963年   3篇
  1941年   2篇
排序方式: 共有325条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
221.
222.
Traditional conceptions of informed consent seem difficult or even impossible to apply to new technologies like biobanks, big data, or GMOs, where vast numbers of people are potentially affected, and where consequences and risks are indeterminate or even unforeseeable. Likewise, the principle has come under strain with the appropriation and monetisation of personal information on digital platforms. Over time, it has largely been reduced to bare assent to formalistic legal agreements. To address the current ineffectiveness of the norm of informed consent, I suggest that we need a notion of structural injustice (on a distinctive interpretation, elaborated here, which takes account of unequal power and property relations). I then argue that in order to protect and enhance people's freedom, we have to go beyond traditional applied ethics and introduce perspectives from democratic theory and social philosophy. I attempt to show how applications of the ‘all‐affected principle’, together with new forms of democratic participation, deliberation, and representation can helpfully frame the narrower principle of informed consent. There is an important role for what we could call collective consent, and informed consent can only succeed in increasing individual agency if it is situated within enhanced forms of democratic decision‐making.  相似文献   
223.
Gestural communications of 10 mild and moderate aphasics and five controls were examined in two conditions: Face-to-face informal dyadic conversation and restricted visual access between speaker and listener. Gestural production was significantly reduced with restriction of visual access, supporting the posited communicative function of the hand and arm gestures investigated in this study. No differences were found between aphasic and control subjects in the rate of gestural communication in the natural condition of face-to-face interaction. Moderate aphasics, however, were found to produce proportionally fewer of the complex semantic modifying and relational communicative gestures and more nonspecific, nonconsensually shared, unclear gestures. Gestural complexity was significantly negatively correlated with measures of linguistic impairment for the aphasics. The relationship between the frequency and complexity of communicative gestures and concurrent verbalizations was also examined. The findings of this study provide confirmation for the view that there is an identifiable class of gestures utilized by aphasics for communication, aphasics are impaired in their gestural communicative competence in natural conditions of communication, and the quality of aphasics' gestural communications parallels changes in their verbal communication patterns.  相似文献   
224.
225.
226.
227.
228.
229.
230.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号