首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   54727篇
  免费   2109篇
  国内免费   21篇
  56857篇
  2019年   580篇
  2018年   914篇
  2017年   823篇
  2016年   919篇
  2015年   623篇
  2014年   819篇
  2013年   4745篇
  2012年   1417篇
  2011年   1491篇
  2010年   891篇
  2009年   952篇
  2008年   1382篇
  2007年   1278篇
  2006年   1196篇
  2005年   1036篇
  2004年   985篇
  2003年   1006篇
  2002年   950篇
  2001年   1801篇
  2000年   1767篇
  1999年   1334篇
  1998年   580篇
  1996年   647篇
  1995年   624篇
  1994年   594篇
  1993年   588篇
  1992年   1300篇
  1991年   1142篇
  1990年   1185篇
  1989年   1038篇
  1988年   1023篇
  1987年   991篇
  1986年   1010篇
  1985年   1042篇
  1984年   885篇
  1983年   738篇
  1982年   579篇
  1981年   576篇
  1979年   848篇
  1978年   650篇
  1975年   776篇
  1974年   822篇
  1973年   892篇
  1972年   796篇
  1971年   703篇
  1970年   610篇
  1969年   615篇
  1968年   777篇
  1967年   663篇
  1966年   677篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
21.
Since 1970 about 80% of the research on oral communication apprehension has used one of two versions of McCroskey's Personal Report of Communication Apprehension. The original 20-item PRCA was introduced for the purpose of measuring apprehension beyond the traditional public speaking context. Although the PRCA-20 is reliable, some serious criticism of it has centered on its ability to tap interpersonal behavior outcomes. In an attempt to bolster its interpersonal applicability, five “interpersonally-oriented” items were added to form the PRCA-25. The studies reported herein demonstrate that both versions fail to possess sufficient reliable variance to be applicable to contexts other than public settings. In addition, it was found that the interpersonal items are a separate component of the PRCA, and as such, do not justify being treated equal in terms of additivity and, therefore, reduce the construct integrity of the PRCA.  相似文献   
22.
23.
24.
In two experiments, hungry rats were given instrumental lever-press training for an appetitive reinforcer and, in addition, were exposed to another type of food which was not contingent on lever pressing. In the first experiment, exposure to each type of food was on separate days, whereas in the second experiment rats were exposed to each type of food in strict alternation within each session. Subsequently, a food aversion was conditioned to the reinforcer for the experimental group and to the non-contingent food for the control group. In both experiments, animals with an aversion to the reinforcer responded less in an extinction test than animals with an aversion to the non-contingent food. Subsequent reacquisition tests confirmed that the aversion to the non-contingent food in the control group was of comparable strength with that to the reinforcer in the experimental group. The results were discussed in terms of whether the reinforcer is encoded in the associative structure set up by exposure to an instrumental contingency.  相似文献   
25.
26.
27.
Although perceived health risk plays a prominent role in theories of health behavior, its empirical role in risk taking is less clear. In Study 1 (N = 129), 2 measures of drivers' risk-taking behavior were found to be unrelated to self-estimates of accident concern but to be related to self-ratings of driving skill and the perceived thrill of driving. In Study 2 (N = 405), out of a wide range of potential influences, accident concern had the weakest relationship with risk taking. The authors concluded that although health risk is a key feature in many theories of health behavior and a central focus for researchers and policy makers, it may not be such a prominent factor for those actually taking the risk.  相似文献   
28.
29.
30.
Do the conditions under which promises are made determine whether they ought to be kept? Philosophers have placed a number of conditions on promising which, they hold, must be met in order to make promise-keeping obligatory. In so doing, they have distinguished valid promises from invalid promises and justified promises from promises that are not justified. Considering such conditions, one by one, we argue that they are mistaken. In the first place, the conditions they lay down are not necessary for either valid or justified promise-making. In the second place, promises need not meet such conditions in order to create moral obligations. In general, such analyses of promising fail because they suffer from a confusion between promise-making and promise-keeping. Philosophers have wrongly supposed that obligations to keep promises are dependent upon, or derivable from, the quality of the promises themselves, at the time they are made, instead of focusing on conditions that must be satisfied at the time when promises are supposed to be kept. It is not the quality of a promise that determines an obligation to keep it but the rightness or wrongness of performing the promised act.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号