首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   17615篇
  免费   717篇
  国内免费   8篇
  18340篇
  2019年   255篇
  2018年   324篇
  2017年   285篇
  2016年   327篇
  2015年   209篇
  2014年   303篇
  2013年   1458篇
  2012年   518篇
  2011年   538篇
  2010年   349篇
  2009年   357篇
  2008年   463篇
  2007年   504篇
  2006年   478篇
  2005年   382篇
  2004年   420篇
  2003年   386篇
  2002年   371篇
  2001年   479篇
  2000年   539篇
  1999年   368篇
  1998年   228篇
  1997年   172篇
  1996年   179篇
  1995年   177篇
  1992年   291篇
  1991年   293篇
  1990年   305篇
  1989年   286篇
  1988年   278篇
  1987年   245篇
  1986年   250篇
  1985年   269篇
  1984年   201篇
  1983年   215篇
  1982年   167篇
  1981年   159篇
  1980年   163篇
  1979年   256篇
  1978年   223篇
  1975年   224篇
  1974年   247篇
  1973年   278篇
  1972年   232篇
  1971年   218篇
  1970年   172篇
  1969年   200篇
  1968年   255篇
  1967年   248篇
  1966年   213篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 0 毫秒
31.
The naming latency of a pronoun was measured when a single previously presented name in a discourse either agreed or did not agree with the pronoun in gender and person. An effect of agreement was found both under conditions in which subjects were likely to have engaged in strategic processing of the pronoun (Experiment 1) and under conditions in which this was unlikely (Experiment 3). The effect of gender agreement was also investigated when two noun phrases were present in the discourse. The results continued to show an immediate effect of gender agreement (naming latencies increased when a pronoun did not agree with one of two previously presented nouns) under experimental conditions likely to engender strategic processing (Experiment 2). This last effect was not significant under experimental conditions that were not likely to engender strategic processing (Experiment 3). The results are discussed in terms of models of the process of identifying the referent of a pronoun in a discourse.  相似文献   
32.
33.
Robertson  Simon 《Synthese》2010,181(1):81-106

What is the relation between what we ought to do, on the one hand, and our epistemic access to the ought-giving facts, on the other? In assessing this, it is common to distinguish ‘objective’ from ‘subjective’ oughts. Very roughly, on the objectivist conception what an agent ought to do is determined by ought-giving facts in such a way that does not depend on the agent’s beliefs about, or epistemic access to, those facts; whereas on the subjectivist conception, what an agent ought to do depends on his beliefs. This paper defends the need for, and explicates, a third category of ‘ought’: ‘warranted oughts’. Section 1 introduces the distinction between objective and subjective ‘oughts’. Sections 2–3 draw attention to some serious problems with each. Section 4 examines, though rejects, a recent attempt to replace subjective ‘oughts’ with objective ‘wide-scope oughts’ operating on belief-action combinations. Section 5 explicates the notion of a warranted ‘ought’ and defends the account against some possible objections. The resulting a picture is one in which an adequate analysis of practical normativity requires both objective and warranted ‘oughts’. Section 6 concludes by responding to a worry about countenancing both.

  相似文献   
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号