首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   510篇
  免费   20篇
  2021年   8篇
  2020年   11篇
  2019年   15篇
  2018年   9篇
  2017年   26篇
  2016年   9篇
  2015年   8篇
  2014年   15篇
  2013年   50篇
  2012年   22篇
  2011年   35篇
  2010年   17篇
  2009年   14篇
  2008年   18篇
  2007年   13篇
  2006年   19篇
  2005年   19篇
  2004年   22篇
  2003年   25篇
  2002年   21篇
  2001年   13篇
  2000年   12篇
  1999年   7篇
  1998年   4篇
  1997年   5篇
  1996年   5篇
  1995年   3篇
  1994年   3篇
  1989年   4篇
  1988年   4篇
  1987年   4篇
  1986年   4篇
  1985年   10篇
  1984年   4篇
  1983年   3篇
  1982年   3篇
  1981年   3篇
  1979年   3篇
  1978年   4篇
  1977年   5篇
  1976年   4篇
  1975年   4篇
  1974年   4篇
  1973年   5篇
  1969年   4篇
  1965年   2篇
  1964年   3篇
  1963年   2篇
  1962年   4篇
  1960年   3篇
排序方式: 共有530条查询结果,搜索用时 46 毫秒
381.
382.
Beddor  Bob 《Philosophical Studies》2020,177(9):2789-2813
Philosophical Studies - According to noncognitivism, normative beliefs are just desire-like attitudes. While noncognitivists have devoted great effort to explaining the nature of normative belief,...  相似文献   
383.
The question of when and how bottom‐up input is integrated with top‐down knowledge has been debated extensively within cognition and perception, and particularly within language processing. A long running debate about the architecture of the spoken‐word recognition system has centered on the locus of lexical effects on phonemic processing: does lexical knowledge influence phoneme perception through feedback, or post‐perceptually in a purely feedforward system? Elman and McClelland (1988) reported that lexically restored ambiguous phonemes influenced the perception of the following phoneme, supporting models with feedback from lexical to phonemic representations. Subsequently, several authors have argued that these results can be fully accounted for by diphone transitional probabilities in a feedforward system (Cairns et al., 1995; Pitt & McQueen, 1998). We report results strongly favoring the original lexical feedback explanation: lexical effects were present even when transitional probability biases were opposite to those of lexical biases.  相似文献   
384.
Can we have a real obligation to the dead, just as we do to the living, or is such a notion merely sentimental or metaphorical? Starting with the example of making a promise, I try to show that we can, since the dead, as well as the living, can have interests, not least because the notion of a person is, in part, a moral construction. ‘The dead’, then, are not merely dead, but particular dead persons, members of something like the sort of ‘transgenerational community’ proposed by Avner de–Shalit. More generally, I argue, we have an obligation to the dead that goes beyond the particularities of promise–making, on account of their role in having made us who we are. I then suggest, though only embryonically, that such obligations may appropriately be discharged by remembering the dead, who they were and what they did. Finally, I consider some possible objections.  相似文献   
385.
386.
Wang  Wei  Zhang  Jie  Lew  Bob 《Journal of religion and health》2021,60(6):4537-4555
Journal of Religion and Health - This study examined the mediating effects of psychological strain (Strain Theory) as a possible explanation for the relationship between religiosity and suicidality...  相似文献   
387.
Extended and distributed cognition theories argue that human cognitive systems sometimes include non-biological objects. On these views, the physical supervenience base of cognitive systems is thus not the biological brain or even the embodied organism, but an organism-plus-artifacts. In this paper, we provide a novel account of the implications of these views for learning, education, and assessment. We start by conceptualizing how we learn to assemble extended cognitive systems by internalizing cultural norms and practices. Having a better grip on how extended cognitive systems are assembled, we focus on the question: If our cognition extends, how should we educate and assess such extended cognitive systems? We suggest various ways to minimize possible negative effects of extending one’s cognition and to efficiently find and organize (online) information by adopting a virtue epistemology approach. Educational and assessment implications are foregrounded, particularly in the case of Danish students’ use of the internet during exams.  相似文献   
388.
389.
390.
Implementation intentions have been shown to effectively change counter‐intentional habits. Research has, however, almost solely been concerned with the effectiveness of a single plan. In the present research, we investigated the behavioral and cognitive implications of making multiple implementation intentions targeting unhealthy snacking habits and its underlying processes, linking multiple habitual snacking cues to healthy alternatives. Study 1 revealed that formulating multiple implementation intentions was not effective in decreasing unhealthy snacking, whereas formulating a single plan successfully induced behavior change. By using a lexical decision task in Study 2, it was found that when making a single plan, but not multiple plans, the healthy alternative became cognitively more accessible in response to a critical cue prime than the habitual response. However, when making additional plans in an unrelated domain, the negative effects of making multiple plans were absent. In sum, the current findings suggest that formulating multiple implementation intentions is ineffective when changing unwanted behavior. These reduced effects of multiple implementation intentions do not occur when making the plan but are rather due to interference in the enacting phase of the planning process. Copyright © 2013 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号