全文获取类型
收费全文 | 676篇 |
免费 | 10篇 |
专业分类
686篇 |
出版年
2023年 | 6篇 |
2022年 | 6篇 |
2021年 | 7篇 |
2020年 | 9篇 |
2019年 | 12篇 |
2018年 | 20篇 |
2017年 | 18篇 |
2016年 | 17篇 |
2015年 | 15篇 |
2014年 | 10篇 |
2013年 | 78篇 |
2012年 | 20篇 |
2011年 | 21篇 |
2010年 | 13篇 |
2009年 | 13篇 |
2008年 | 20篇 |
2007年 | 25篇 |
2006年 | 13篇 |
2005年 | 13篇 |
2004年 | 9篇 |
2003年 | 31篇 |
2002年 | 18篇 |
2001年 | 18篇 |
2000年 | 24篇 |
1999年 | 12篇 |
1998年 | 9篇 |
1997年 | 6篇 |
1996年 | 8篇 |
1995年 | 8篇 |
1992年 | 8篇 |
1991年 | 10篇 |
1990年 | 7篇 |
1988年 | 12篇 |
1987年 | 8篇 |
1986年 | 9篇 |
1985年 | 7篇 |
1984年 | 5篇 |
1983年 | 5篇 |
1981年 | 5篇 |
1979年 | 14篇 |
1978年 | 6篇 |
1976年 | 5篇 |
1975年 | 5篇 |
1974年 | 13篇 |
1973年 | 14篇 |
1972年 | 6篇 |
1970年 | 6篇 |
1969年 | 6篇 |
1968年 | 6篇 |
1966年 | 5篇 |
排序方式: 共有686条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
261.
The authors evaluated whether an incentive raffle increased teachers' use of written praise and appropriate student behavior. Participants included 93 staff members and 755 students at an elementary school in Central Illinois. School staff received didactic instruction for the importance of using praise, and praise notes were measured on a weekly basis by praise type, staff member type, and student type. Results indicated that the faculty incentive produced medium effects for praise for students, but did not impact the number of office discipline referrals. Staff members reported praise notes to be an acceptable school-wide system for managing student behavior, but had mixed feelings regarding faculty receiving incentives for writing praise notes. Implications as well as future research are discussed. 相似文献
262.
In two experiments, we investigated the processing of extrafoveal objects in a double-object naming task. On most trials, participants named two objects; but on some trials, the objects were replaced shortly after trial onset by a written word probe, which participants had to name instead of the objects. In Experiment 1, the word was presented in the same location as the left object either 150 or 350 msec after trial onset and was either phonologically related or unrelated to that object name. Phonological facilitation was observed at the later but not at the earlier SOA. In Experiment 2, the word was either phonologically related or unrelated to the right object and was presented 150 msec after the speaker had begun to inspect that object. In contrast with Experiment 1, phonological facilitation was found at this early SOA, demonstrating that the speakers had begun to process the right object prior to fixation. 相似文献
263.
264.
The main purpose of this study was to examine potential within-group differences in well-being in individuals who experienced postlingual, late deafness between the ages of 13 and 65 years old. Two related issues were also examined: (a) the psychometric qualities of 2 popular measures of well-being when used with this sample and (b) the well-being of individuals who are late deafened compared to normative data on well-being. A sample of 138 women who were late deafened completed an online survey. The results indicated internal consistency and validity (convergent and partial discriminant) of the 2 well-being measures with this sample. Well-being in this sample was significantly lower than that in samples from the general population. Investigation of within-group differences indicated that individuals from lower socioeconomic groups reported lower levels of well-being. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2010 APA, all rights reserved). 相似文献
265.
Robert K. Meyer 《Journal of Philosophical Logic》2008,37(2):169-181
C I Lewis showed up Down Under in 2005, in e-mails initiated by Allen Hazen of Melbourne. Their topic was the system Hazen
called FL (a Funny Logic), axiomatized in passing in Lewis 1921. I show that FL is the system MEN of material equivalence with negation.
But negation plays no special role in MEN. Symbolizing equivalence with → and defining ∼A inferentially as A→f, the theorems of MEN are just those of the underlying theory ME of pure material equivalence. This accords with the treatment
of negation in the Abelian l-group logic A of Meyer and Slaney (Abelian logic. Abstract, Journal of Symbolic Logic 46, 425–426, 1981), which also defines ∼A inferentially with no special conditions on
f. The paper then concentrates on the pure implicational part AI of A, the simple logic of Abelian groups. The integers Z were known to be characteristic for AI, with every non-theorem B refutable mod some Zn for finite n. Noted here is that AI is pre-tabular, having the Scroggs property that every proper extension SI of AI, closed under substitution and detachment, has some finite
Zn as its characteristic matrix. In particular FL is the extension for which n = 2 (Lewis, The structure of logic and its relation to other systems. The Journal of Philosophy 18, 505–516, 1921; Meyer and Slaney, Abelian logic. Abstract. Journal of Symbolic Logic 46, 425–426, 1981; This is an abstract of the much longer paper finally published in 1989 in G. G. Priest, R. Routley and J.
Norman, eds., Paraconsistent logic: essays on the inconsistent, Philosophica Verlag, Munich, pp. 245–288, 1989).
Meyer was supported in this work as a Visiting Fellow in the College of Engineering and Computer Science, ANU. 相似文献
266.
267.
268.
This waitlist-controlled study evaluated the efficacy of a short version of a group CBT for BED followed by booster sessions after the active treatment phase. Thirty-six females with BED were randomly assigned to CBT (eight weekly sessions during active treatment plus five booster sessions during follow-up) or a waitlist condition. At the end of the active treatment, binge eating was significantly reduced relative to waitlist. Furthermore, at 12-month follow-up short-term CBT produced significant improvements in binge eating symptoms relative to baseline. Findings suggest that the short-term CBT followed by booster sessions may provide a valuable treatment option for patients with BED. 相似文献
269.
The aim of the work is to provide a language to reason about Closed Interactions, i.e. all those situations in which the outcomes
of an interaction can be determined by the agents themselves and in which the environment cannot interfere with they are able
to determine. We will see that two different interpretations can be given of this restriction, both stemming from Pauly Representation
Theorem. We will identify such restrictions and axiomatize their logic. We will apply the formal tools to reason about games
and their regulation. 相似文献
270.
Richard Booth Thomas Meyer Chattrakul Sombattheera 《Journal of Philosophical Logic》2012,41(4):711-733
Most belief change operators in the AGM tradition assume an underlying plausibility ordering over the possible worlds which is transitive and complete. A unifying structure for these operators, based on supplementing the plausibility ordering with a second, guiding, relation over the worlds was presented in Booth et al. (Artif Intell 174:1339–1368, 2010). However it is not always reasonable to assume completeness of the underlying ordering. In this paper we generalise the structure of Booth et al. (Artif Intell 174:1339–1368, 2010) to allow incomparabilities between worlds. We axiomatise the resulting class of belief removal functions, and show that it includes an important family of removal functions based on finite prioritised belief bases. 相似文献