全文获取类型
收费全文 | 1706篇 |
免费 | 45篇 |
专业分类
1751篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 8篇 |
2023年 | 13篇 |
2022年 | 19篇 |
2021年 | 25篇 |
2020年 | 61篇 |
2019年 | 59篇 |
2018年 | 82篇 |
2017年 | 67篇 |
2016年 | 89篇 |
2015年 | 74篇 |
2014年 | 76篇 |
2013年 | 214篇 |
2012年 | 126篇 |
2011年 | 103篇 |
2010年 | 83篇 |
2009年 | 79篇 |
2008年 | 90篇 |
2007年 | 64篇 |
2006年 | 44篇 |
2005年 | 43篇 |
2004年 | 68篇 |
2003年 | 42篇 |
2002年 | 39篇 |
2001年 | 21篇 |
2000年 | 13篇 |
1999年 | 11篇 |
1998年 | 10篇 |
1997年 | 5篇 |
1996年 | 7篇 |
1995年 | 3篇 |
1994年 | 5篇 |
1993年 | 10篇 |
1992年 | 4篇 |
1991年 | 4篇 |
1990年 | 7篇 |
1989年 | 7篇 |
1988年 | 4篇 |
1984年 | 4篇 |
1982年 | 5篇 |
1981年 | 4篇 |
1980年 | 7篇 |
1979年 | 4篇 |
1978年 | 4篇 |
1977年 | 3篇 |
1976年 | 10篇 |
1975年 | 5篇 |
1974年 | 4篇 |
1973年 | 3篇 |
1968年 | 4篇 |
1966年 | 3篇 |
排序方式: 共有1751条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
21.
Both contact contamination (CC) and mental contamination (MC) fears—which combined represent the most common manifestation of obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD)—have been widely associated with disgust propensity. However, extant research explored this relationship using measures assessing only pathogen-related disgust, not taking into account the potential role played by sexual and moral disgust, despite literature about MC suggesting that this might be particularly relevant. In Study 1, the psychometric properties of the Italian version of the Three Domains of Disgust Scale (TDDS) were assessed in a large Italian community sample. Exploratory and confirmatory factor analyses confirmed the three-factor structure of the TDDS. The scale also showed good internal consistency and construct validity. In Study 2, the differential patterns of relationships between CC and MC and the three disgust domains were explored in an Italian clinical OCD sample using a path analytic approach. The TDDS-Pathogen subscale was a unique predictor of CC while the TDDS-Sexual subscale was a unique predictor of MC, after controlling for anxiety and depression. Surprisingly, the TDDS-Moral subscale was not a predictor of either domain of contamination fear. Limitations and clinical implications are discussed. 相似文献
22.
A conspicuous oversight in recent debates about the vexed problem of the value of knowledge has been the value of knowledge-how. This would not be surprising if knowledge-how were, as Gilbert Ryle [1945, 1949] famously thought, fundamentally different from knowledge-that. However, reductive intellectualists [e.g. Stanley and Williamson 2001; Brogaard 2008, 2009, 2011; Stanley 2011a, 2011b] maintain that knowledge-how just is a kind of knowledge-that. Accordingly, reductive intellectualists must predict that the value problems facing propositional knowledge will equally apply to knowledge-how. We show, however, that this is not the case. Accordingly, we highlight a value-driven argument for thinking (contra reductive intellectualism) that knowledge-how and knowledge-that come apart. 相似文献
23.
Innovation in the Greek Orthodox Tradition? The Question of Change in Greek Orthodox Thought and Practice edited by Trine Stauning Willert and Lina Molokotos‐Liederman (eds.), Ashgate, 2012 (ISBN 978‐1‐4094‐2077‐4), xiv + 284 pp., hb £55
下载免费PDF全文

Adam A. J. DeVille 《Reviews in Religion & Theology》2015,22(1):90-93
24.
25.
26.
Kirk Heilbrun William S. Bennett Adam J. White Jennifer Kelly 《Behavioral sciences & the law》1990,8(1):45-53
The empirically-based model of malingering and deception described by Rogers (1984b) was operationalized using MMPI and clinical interview data. Subjects (N = 159) were patients committed to an inpatient forensic hospital as ‘Incompetent to Stand Trial’ or ‘Not Guilty by Reason of Insanity’. Inter-rater reliability was acceptable for the 11 criteria used to define response styles. Each subject was categorized into one of five response style groups: ‘Reliable’, ‘Malingering’, ‘Defensive’, ‘Irrelevant’, or ‘Unclassifiable’. Factor analysis of the rating criteria yielded four factors, three of which are comparable to the assigned groups, providing some validation for the constructs underlying these groups. 相似文献
27.
Adam Hosein 《Res Publica》2017,23(3):367-385
The role of responsibility in our common-sense morality of self-defense is complex. According to common-sense morality, one can sometimes use substantial, even deadly, force against people who are only minimally responsible for posing a threat to us. The role of responsibility in self-defense is thus limited. However, responsibility is still sometimes relevant. It sometime affects how much force you can use against a threatener: less if they are less responsible and more if they are more responsible. Is there a well-motivated theory that can explain both why the role of responsibility is limited and why it is sometimes relevant? It is hard to see what theory could unify these disparate elements of our common-sense morality, and if one cannot be found then we may simply have to revise some of our pre-theoretic beliefs. But it would be an important advantage of a theory if it could justify those beliefs. I will argue that there is a theory of this kind: surprisingly, the familiar rights theory of self-defense, defended by Judith Thomson, can do so if it is suitably supplemented. Along the way I will survey some alternative theories of self-defense and show why they are not up to the task. 相似文献
28.
29.
30.