共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
2.
A recent group of social scientists have argued that counterfactual questions play an essential role in their disciplines,
and that it is possible to have rigorous methods to investigate them. Unfortunately, there has been little (if any) interaction
between these social scientists and the philosophers who have long held that rigorous counterfactual reasoning is possible.
In this paper, I hope to encourage some fresh thinking on both sides by creating new connections between them. I describe
what I term “problem of selecting antecedent scenarios,” and show that this is an essential challenge in real-life counterfactual
reasoning. Then, I demonstrate that the major extant theories of counterfactuals (especially the Lewis/Stalnaker theory and
Igal Kvart’s rival account) are unable to solve this problem. I show that there are instances of real-life counterfactual
reasoning in the social sciences that are counterexamples to both of these accounts. And finally, I develop a new theory of
how to select antecedent scenarios that overcomes these difficulties, and so would be part of a more adequate theory of counterfactuals
(and counterfactual reasoning). 相似文献
3.
Donald Bamber 《Journal of mathematical psychology》1979,19(2):137-181
An independent variable measures some aspect of a treatment applied to a person; a dependent variable measures some aspect of the treatment's effect upon the person. Two dependent variables will often covary with each other because they are affected by a common independent variable. A state trace is a graph which plots the value of one dependent variable as a function of another. (Thus, a state trace is a generalization of the yes-no receiver-operating-characteristic curve.) By appropriately analyzing state traces, it is possible to test theories concerning (a) the mechanisms by which independent variables affect dependent variables and (b) how these mechanisms differ from one population of persons to another. As an illustration, a study of long-term memory in normal persons, schizophrenics, and persons with organic brain syndrome is presented. The effects of number of word presentations and length of retention interval upon probability of word recall and recognition were investigated. The results were analyzed by state-trace analysis. 相似文献
4.
5.
In this journal (AJP 2016), Vishnu Sridharan presents a novel objection to attributionism, the view according to which agents are responsible for their conduct when it reflects who they are or what they value. The key to Sridharan's objection is that agents can fulfil all attributionist conditions for responsibility while being under the control of a manipulator. In this paper, we show that Sridharan's objection falls prey to a dilemma—either his manipulator is counterfactually robust, or she is not—and that neither of its horns undermines attributionism. 相似文献
6.
Gary Ostertag 《Philosophical Studies》2009,146(2):249-267
Russellianism is characterized as the view that ‘that’-clauses refer to Russellian propositions, familiar set-theoretic pairings
of objects and properties. Two belief-reporting sentences, S and S*, possessing the same Russellian content, but differing in their intuitive truthvalue, are provided. It is argued that no
Russellian explanation of the difference in apparent truthvalue is available, with the upshot that the Russellian fails to
explain how a speaker who asserts S but rejects S* can be innocent of inconsistency, either in what she says or, at least,
in what she implicates. Yet, while there is no semantic or pragmatic explanation of the substitution failure consistent with
Russellianism, there remains the possibility of a purely psychological explanation that is, nonetheless, Russellian. This
is an attractive option. It comes at a cost, however, since, in abandoning the project of providing a semantic or pragmatic
explanation of anti-substitutivity intuitions, the Russellian is no longer in the business of explaining how a rational, well-informed
speaker, with no incentive to mislead, can avoid inconsistency in reporting the facts as they appear. 相似文献
7.
Sungho Choi 《Erkenntnis》2007,67(1):1-16
Recently Stephen Barker has raised stimulating objections to the thesis that, roughly speaking, if two events stand in a relation
of counterfactual dependence, they stand in a causal relation. As Ned Hall says, however, this thesis constitutes the strongest
part of the counterfactual analysis of causation. Therefore, if successful, Barker’s objections will undermine the cornerstone
of the counterfactual analysis of causation, and hence give us compelling reasons to reject the counterfactual analysis of
causation. I will argue, however, that they do not withstand scrutiny. 相似文献
8.
9.
Journal of Philosophical Logic - This paper is concerned with counterfactual logic and its implications for the modal status of mathematical claims. It is most directly a response to an ambitious... 相似文献
10.
11.
本文指出了von Fintel(2001)和Gillies(2007)中对反事实条件句序列处理中的两个问题,尤其是反事实条件句与事实句的相互作用问题。然后,我们在动态语义框架中对反事实条件句给出了一个新的语义解释,并且表明von Fintel和Gillies理论中的问题能够被解决。 相似文献
12.
13.
Alex Broadbent 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2013,21(2):169-189
The counterfactual analysis of causation has focused on one particular counterfactual conditional, taking as its starting‐point the suggestion that C causes E iff (~C □→ ~E). In this paper, some consequences are explored of reversing this counterfactual, and developing an account starting with the idea that C causes E iff (~E □→ ~C). This suggestion is discussed in relation to the problem of pre‐emption. It is found that the ‘reversed’ counterfactual analysis can handle even the most difficult cases of pre‐emption with only minimal complications. The paper closes with a discussion of the wider philosophical implications of developing a reversed counterfactual analysis, especially concerning the differentiation of causes from causal conditions, causation by absences, and the extent to which causes suffice for their effects. 相似文献
14.
Most people believe that they should avoid changing their answer when taking multiple-choice tests. Virtually all research on this topic, however, has suggested that this strategy is ill-founded: Most answer changes are from incorrect to correct, and people who change their answers usually improve their test scores. Why do people believe in this strategy if the data so strongly refute it? The authors argue that the belief is in part a product of counterfactual thinking. Changing an answer when one should have stuck with one's original answer leads to more "if only . . ." self-recriminations than does sticking with one's first instinct when one should have switched. As a consequence, instances of the former are more memorable than instances of the latter. This differential availability provides individuals with compelling (albeit illusory) personal evidence for the wisdom of always following their 1st instinct, with suboptimal test scores the result. 相似文献
15.
Roese N 《Psychonomic bulletin & review》1999,6(4):570-578
Recent research on counterfactual thinking is discussed in terms of its implications for decision making. Against a backdrop of the functional benefits of counterfactual thinking, two distinct types of bias, one liberal and one conservative, are discussed. Counterfactuals may cause decision makers to become liberally biased (i.e., capricious) in terms of tactics, but conservatively biased (i.e., rigid) in terms of long-term strategy. That is, counterfactuals may lead to short-term corrective changes that are needless and costly, but they may also lead to long-term overconfidence, blinding the decision maker to possible beneficial strategic adjustments. Recent research on counterfactual thinking, which is inherently multidisciplinary, is reviewed in light of a theoretical structure that posits two mechanisms by which counterfactual effects occur: contrast effects and causal inferences. 相似文献
16.
Jens Harbecke 《Philosophia》2014,42(2):363-385
Counterfactual conditionals have been appealed to in various ways to show how the mind can be causally efficacious. However, it has often been overestimated what the truth of certain counterfactuals actually indicates about causation. The paper first identifies four approaches that seem to commit precisely this mistake. The arguments discussed involve erroneous assumptions about the connection of counterfactual dependence and genuine causation, as well as a disregard of the requisite evaluation conditions of counterfactuals. In a second step, the paper uses the insights of the foregoing analyses to formulate a set of counterfactuals-based conditions that are characterized as sufficient to establish singular causal claims. The paper concludes that there are ample reasons to believe that some mental events satisfy all these conditions with respect to certain further events and, hence, that mental events sometimes are causes. 相似文献
17.
Counterfactual and prefactual conditionals. 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
We consider reasoning about prefactual possibilities in the future, for example, "if I were to win the lottery next year I would buy a yacht" and counterfactual possibilities, for example, "if I had won the lottery last year, I would have bought a yacht." People may reason about indicative conditionals, for example, "if I won the lottery I bought a yacht" by keeping in mind a few true possibilities, for example, "I won the lottery and I bought a yacht." They understand counterfactuals by keeping in mind two possibilities, the conjecture, "I won the lottery and I bought a yacht" and the presupposed facts, "I did not win the lottery and I did not buy a yacht." We report the results of three experiments on prefactuals that examine what people judge them to imply, the possibilities they judge to be consistent with them, and the inferences they judge to follow from them. The results show that reasoners keep a single possibility in mind to understand a prefactual. 相似文献
18.
19.
20.