共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
2.
Carla Bagnoli 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》2018,21(4):851-868
This paper argues that to understand the varieties of wrongs done in coercion, we should examine the dynamic normative relation that the coercer establishes with the coerced. The case rests on a critical examination of coercion by threat, which is proved irreducible to psychological inducement by overwhelming motives, obstruction of agency by impaired consent or deprivation of genuine choice. In contrast to physical coercion, coercion by threat requires the coercee’s participation in deliberation to succeed. For this kind of coercion to be successful, there must be a normative relation established by the coercer and the coercee, in which they recognize each other as rational agents. In such cases, the coercee is wronged in the exercise of her deliberative powers. As a consequence, this form of coercion does not cancel the coercee’s moral responsibility for coerced action. Reclaiming the coercee’s responsibility for action under threat does not diminish the visibility and gravity of the coercer’s wrongdoing. On the contrary, it allows us to capture some features of the coercive relation that otherwise remain unfocused and thus identify the distinctive ways in which the coercee is wronged. 相似文献
3.
ROBERT CAMPBELL 《Journal of applied philosophy》1984,1(1):133-140
ABSTRACT Not all crimes require mens rea, but all serious ones do. Crudely the requirement is that the defendant be able to take responsibility for the actus reus of which he is accused. What must be implied by this is essentially that the agent retain control of his actions. It is unjust to punish actions which are outside of the agent's control since such punishment cannot deter and is, arguably, pointless.
Duress does not remove an agent's control of his actions. This does not mean that actions performed under duress should be viewed as fully intentional. For though the agent foresees and wishes for the result of his action performed under duress, it is wished for as the best option out of a range of alternatives manipulated by the one who makes the threats which constitute the duress. The agent is responsible for his choice, but not for what is available for him to choose. He has an obligation to do what is best in the circumstances and should not be blamed if that would, in other circumstances, be accounted criminal. 相似文献
Duress does not remove an agent's control of his actions. This does not mean that actions performed under duress should be viewed as fully intentional. For though the agent foresees and wishes for the result of his action performed under duress, it is wished for as the best option out of a range of alternatives manipulated by the one who makes the threats which constitute the duress. The agent is responsible for his choice, but not for what is available for him to choose. He has an obligation to do what is best in the circumstances and should not be blamed if that would, in other circumstances, be accounted criminal. 相似文献
4.
5.
CARL ELLIOTT 《Journal of applied philosophy》1991,8(1):45-56
ABSTRACT The paper is a discussion of moral responsibility and excuses in regard to psychiatric disorders involving abnormal desires (e.g. impulse control disorders such as kleptomania and pyromania, psychosexual disorders such as exhibitionism, obsessive-compulsive disorder and others). It points out problems with previous approaches to the question of whether or not to excuse persons with these disorders, and offers a new approach based on the concept of duress. There is a discussion of duress in regard to non-psychiatric cases based on the core notion of duress involving a choice between undesirables, and the paper concludes with an argument that moral blame for individuals with these sorts of disorders should often be lessened and in some cases removed entirely. 相似文献
6.
7.
Since 1984, sexual abuse by Catholic clergy has captured public attention and resulted in a stream of criminal and civil lawsuits. The hierarchy has been defensive in the face of constant accusations and criticism. This study examines selected key aspects of the clergy sex abuse phenomenon including historical precedents and the impact of clericalism on the development of psychological and emotional duress in victims and others closely associated with sexual abuse. 相似文献
8.
9.
《Psychoanalytic Social Work》2013,20(2):41-55
Abstract “Forced termination” of psychoanalysis occurs when the analyst electively terminates the treatment for reasons of his own, independent of the clinical indications for termination. The author describes his own experience with the forced termination of his training analysis. The literature is reviewed, with an emphasis on the attitude of each author regarding the straggle around the decision. The author explores sources of general ethical knowledge, the ethical foundations of the analyst-analysand relation ship, and the application of these ideas to psychoanalysis. From these princi ples, the ethical problems of forced termination are derived and examined. The author proposes reforms to address these problems. 相似文献
10.
11.
Ira Kiourti 《Philosophical Studies》2008,139(3):343-352
In her (1996) Kadri Vihvelin argues that autoinfanticide is nomologically impossible and so that there is no sense in which time travelers
are able to commit it. In response, Theodore Sider (2002) defends the original Lewisian verdict (Lewis 1976) whereby, on a common understanding of ability, time travelers are able to kill their earlier selves and their failure to
do so is merely coincidental. This paper constitutes a critical note on arguments put forward by both Sider and Vihvelin.
I argue that although Sider’s criticism starts out promisingly he doesn’t succeed in establishing that Vihvelin’s analysis
fails, because (a) he neglects to rule out a class of counterfactuals to which Vihvelin’s sample-case may belong; and (b)
(together with Lewis) he is wrong to suggest that future facts are irrelevant in the evaluation of time travelers’ abilities.
I show instead that Vihvelin’s argument is viciously circular, indicating that even if there are nomological constraints on
autoinfanticide these cannot be established a priori.
相似文献
Ira KiourtiEmail: |
12.
13.
Religious duress is a unique kind of threat and constraint involuntarily experienced by some members of the Roman Catholic
Church as a result of religious indoctrination and training. Fear, awe and respect for the clergy foster the development and
actualization of religious duress. This phenomenon can seriously impede a person’s capacity to accurately perceive and evaluate abusive actions perpetrated
on them by clergy. This constraint poses an impediment to emotional and spiritual development. Internalized religious duress
confuses and psychologically overwhelms such individuals and renders them incapable of absorbing their sexual trauma. The
consequent feelings of numbness and immobility distort the perception of reality. It then becomes impossible for the individual
to act in a manner that would protect and promote emotional growth and spiritual well being. 相似文献
14.
15.
16.
DENNIS MCKERLIE 《Philosophy and phenomenological research》2005,71(2):477-490
17.
Peter Singer 《Inquiry (Oslo, Norway)》2013,56(1-4):145-156
It is one thing to say that the suffering of non‐human animals ought to be considered equally with the like suffering of humans; quite another to decide how the wrongness of killing non‐human animals compares with the wrongness of killing human beings. It is argued that while species makes no difference to the wrongness of killing, the possession of certain capacities, in particular the capacity to see oneself as a distinct entity with a future, does. It is claimed, however, that this is not the only factor to be taken into account: pleasant or happy life is in itself good. The application of these conclusions to killing animals for food is then considered, with some passing reflections on infanticide. 相似文献
18.
19.
Jeff McMahan 《Philosophia》2006,34(1):23-41
This paper argues that certain central tenets of the traditional theory of the just war cannot be correct. It then advances an alternative account grounded in the same considerations of justice that govern self-defense at the individual level. The implications of this account are unorthodox. It implies that, with few exceptions, combatants who fight for an unjust cause act impermissibly when they attack enemy combatants, and that combatants who fight in a just war may, in certain circumstances, legitimately target noncombatants who bear a significant degree of moral responsibility for a wrong, when the prevention or rectification of that wrong constitutes a just cause for war.
相似文献
Jeff McMahanEmail: |
20.
Nils Holtug 《The Journal of Ethics》2011,15(3):169-189
Jeff McMahan appeals to what he calls the “Time-relative Interest Account of the Wrongness of Killing” to explain the wrongness
of killing individuals who are conscious but not autonomous. On this account, the wrongness of such killing depends on the
victim’s interest in his or her future, and this interest, in turn, depends on two things: the goods that would have accrued
to the victim in the future; and the strength of the prudential relations obtaining between the victim at the time of the
killing and at the times these goods would have accrued to him or her. More precisely, when assessing this interest, future
goods should be discounted to reflect reductions in the strength of such relations. Against McMahan’s account I argue that
it relies on an implausible “actualist” view of the moral importance of interests according to which satisfactions of future
interests only have moral significance if they are satisfactions of actual interests (interests that will in fact exist).
More precisely, I aim to show that the Time-relative Interest Account (1) does not have the implications for the morality
of killing that McMahan takes it to have, and (2) implies, implausibly, that certain interest satisfactions which seem to
be morally significant are morally insignificant because they are not satisfactions of actual interests. 相似文献