共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
Truthmaking, Entailment, and the Conjunction Thesis 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
3.
Chris Ranalli 《Synthese》2014,191(6):1223-1247
Looking out the window, I see that it’s raining outside. Do I know that it’s raining outside? According to proponents of the Entailment Thesis, I do. If I see that p, I know that p. In general, the Entailment Thesis is the thesis that if S perceives that p, S knows that p. But recently, some philosophers (McDowell, in Smith (ed.) Reading McDowell on mind and world, 2002; Turri, Theoria 76(3):197–206, 2010; Pritchard, Philos Issues (Supplement to Nous) 21:434–455, 2011; Pritchard, Epistemological disjunctivism, 2012) have argued that the Entailment Thesis is false. On their view, we can see p and not know that p. In this paper, I argue that their arguments are unsuccessful. 相似文献
4.
Richard Menary 《Topoi》2009,28(1):31-43
Naturalistic philosophers ought to think that the mind is continuous with the rest of the world and should not, therefore,
be surprised by the findings of the extended mind, cognitive integration and enactivism. Not everyone is convinced that all
mental phenomena are continuous with the rest of the world. For example, intentionality is often formulated in a way that
makes the mind discontinuous with the rest of the world. This is a consequence of Brentano’s formulation of intentionality,
I suggest, and can be overcome by revealing that the concept of intentional directedness as he receives it from the Scholastics
is quite consistent with the continuity thesis. It is only when intentional directedness is conjoined with intentional inexistence
that intentionality and content are consistent with a discontinuity thesis (such as Brentano’s thesis). This makes room to
develop an account of intentional directedness that is consistent with the continuity thesis in the form of Peirce’s representational
principle. I also argue against a form of the discontinuity thesis in the guise of the derived/underived content distinction.
Having shown that intentionality is consistent with the continuity thesis I argue that we should focus on intentionality and
representation as bodily enacted. I conclude that we would be better off focussing on representation and intentionality in
action rather than giving abstract functional accounts of extended cognition.
相似文献
Richard MenaryEmail: |
5.
6.
7.
Jon Garthoff 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》2004,7(1):15-29
In this essay I articulate and defend a thesis about the nature of morality called “the embodiment thesis”. The embodiment
thesis states that moral values underdetermine the obligations and entitlements of individual persons, and that actual social
institutions must embody morality by specifying these moral relations. I begin by presenting two thought experiments that
elucidate and motivate the embodiment thesis. I then proceed by distinguishing the embodiment thesis from a Rawlsian doctrine
about the nature of justice, from the doctrine of moral relativism, and from solutions to the coordination problem of rational
choice theory. 相似文献
8.
9.
10.
Ethan Brauer 《Pacific Philosophical Quarterly》2023,104(3):494-510
The problem of peer disagreement is to explain how you should respond when you and a peer have the same evidence bearing on some proposition and are equally competent epistemic agents, yet have reached opposite conclusions about . According to Christensen's Independence Thesis, in assessing the effect of your peer's disagreement, you must not rely on the reasoning behind your initial belief. I note that ‘the reasoning behind your initial belief’ can be given either a token or type reading. I argue that the type reading is false, but the token reading is extremely weak. 相似文献
11.
Rudolph L 《Integrative psychological & behavioral science》2008,42(2):144-152
I suggest a modification—and mathematization—of Freeman’s thesis on the relations among “perception”, “the finite brain”,
and “the world”, based on my recent proposal that the theory of finite topological spaces is both an adequate and a natural
mathematical foundation for human psychology.
Lee Rudolph is Professor of Mathematics at Clark University and an affiliate of the Kitchen Seminar and SEC Forum there. Most of his mathematical research (since his 1974 Ph.D. from M.I.T.) has been in low-dimensional geometric topology, which he has recently begun to apply to both mathematical psychology and robotics. He currently a co-principal investigator of Practical Parametrization and Efficient Motion Planning of Linkage Systems (NSF Award IIS-0713335). His third collection of poetry, A Woman and a Man, Ice-Fishing, was published by Texas Review Press in 2005. 相似文献
Lee RudolphEmail: URL: http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~lrudolph |
Lee Rudolph is Professor of Mathematics at Clark University and an affiliate of the Kitchen Seminar and SEC Forum there. Most of his mathematical research (since his 1974 Ph.D. from M.I.T.) has been in low-dimensional geometric topology, which he has recently begun to apply to both mathematical psychology and robotics. He currently a co-principal investigator of Practical Parametrization and Efficient Motion Planning of Linkage Systems (NSF Award IIS-0713335). His third collection of poetry, A Woman and a Man, Ice-Fishing, was published by Texas Review Press in 2005. 相似文献
12.
13.
14.
David Copp 《Journal of social philosophy》2007,38(3):369-388
15.
16.
Despite extensive research on the subject spanning over 70 years, uncertainty still remains as to whether happier workers
are in fact more productive. This study combined longitudinal prospective and experience sampling methods to examine the relationship
between happiness and self-reported productivity among Directors employed in the public and private sectors. Analyses at a
trait level suggested happy people were more productive. Similarly, at the state level of analysis, people were more productive
when they were happier. Among the happiness indicators examined (job satisfaction, quality of work life, life satisfaction,
positive affect, and negative affect) positive affect was most strongly, but not exclusively, tied to productivity at both
the state and trait levels. Discussion focuses on reconciling a long history of mixed findings regarding the happy-productive
worker thesis.
相似文献
John M. ZelenskiEmail: |
17.
18.
Synthese - Hoyningen-Huene (Systematicity: the nature of science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013) develops an account of what science is, distinguishing it from common sense. According to... 相似文献
19.
20.
If the arrow → stands for classical relevant implication, Aristotle's Thesis ¬(A→¬A) is inconsistent with the Law of Simplification (AB)→B accepted by relevantists, but yields an inconsistent non-trivial extension of the system of entailment E. Such paraconsistent extensions of relevant logics have been studied by R. Routley, C. Mortensen and R. Brady. After examining the semantics associated to such systems, it is stressed that there are nonclassical treatments of relevance which do not support Simplification. The paper aims at showing that Aristotle's Thesis may receive a sense if the arrow is defined as strict implication endowed with the proviso that the clauses of the conditional have the same modal status, i.e. the same position in the Aristotelian square. It is so grasped, in different form, the basic idea of relevant logic that the clauses of a true conditional should have something in common. It is proved that thanks to such definition of the arrow Aristotle's Thesis subjoined to the minimal normal system K yields a system equivalent to the deontic system KD. 相似文献