共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
Kourken Michaelian 《Erkenntnis》2011,74(3):399-424
The default view in the epistemology of forgetting is that human memory would be epistemically better if we were not so susceptible
to forgetting—that forgetting is in general a cognitive vice. In this paper, I argue for the opposed view: normal human forgetting—the
pattern of forgetting characteristic of cognitively normal adult human beings—approximates a virtue located at the mean between
the opposed cognitive vices of forgetting too much and remembering too much. I argue, first, that, for any finite cognizer,
a certain pattern of forgetting is necessary if her memory is to perform its function well. I argue, second, that, by eliminating
“clutter” from her memory store, this pattern of forgetting improves the overall shape of the subject’s total doxastic state.
I conclude by reviewing work in psychology which suggests that normal human forgetting approximates this virtuous pattern
of forgetting. 相似文献
4.
Barry Stroud 《Erkenntnis》2011,75(3):495-503
A brief discussion of the ways in which awareness of and sensitivity to the history of philosophy can contribute to epistemology
even if epistemology is understood as a distinctively philosophical and not primarily historical enterprise. 相似文献
5.
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research - Moral epistemology (henceforth ME) has been spoken of as a subject matter in its own right by philosophers in the last few decades and yet the... 相似文献
6.
JOEL J. KUPPERMAN 《Philosophy and phenomenological research》2005,70(3):659-680
Might there be knowledge of non‐instrumental values? Arguments are give for two principal claims. One is that if there is such knowledge, it typically will have features that do not entirely match those of other kinds of knowledge. It will have a closer relation to the kind of person one is or becomes, and in the way it combines features of knowing‐how with knowing‐that. There also are problems of indeterminacy of non‐instrumental value which are not commonly found in other things that we can know about. The second claim is that there is a strong prima‐facie case for holding that there is such knowledge, and that the usual arguments against this are all faulty. 相似文献
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
Patrick R. Frierson 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2016,94(1):79-98
This paper shows how Maria Montessori's thought can enrich contemporary virtue epistemology. After a short overview of her ‘interested empiricist’ epistemological framework, I discuss four representative intellectual virtues: sensory acuity, physical dexterity, intellectual love, and intellectual humility. Throughout, I show how Montessori bridges the divide between reliabilist and responsibilist approaches to the virtues and how her particular treatments of virtues offer distinctive and compelling alternatives to contemporary accounts. For instance, she emphasizes how sensory acuity is a virtue for which one can be responsible, highlights the embodied nature of cognition through a focus on physical dexterity, interprets intellectual love as a way of loving the world rather than as a love that takes knowledge as its object, and presents an alternative account of intellectual humility to contemporary emphases on the interpersonal dimensions of this virtue. 相似文献
13.
In this paper I argue, first, that the most influential (and perhaps only acceptable) account of the epistemology of self-knowledge,
developed and defended at great length in Wright (1989b) and (1989c) (among other places), leaves unanswered a question about
the psychology of self-knowledge; second, that without an answer to this question about the psychology of self-knowledge,
the epistemic account cannot be considered acceptable; and third, that neither Wright's own answer, nor an interpretation-based
answer (based on a proposal from Jacobsen (1997)), will suffice as an acceptable answer to the psychological question. My
general ambition is thus to establish that more work is needed if we are to have a full account of self-knowledge in both
its epistemological and psychological aspects. I conclude by suggesting how my thesis bears on those who aim to provide an
empirical account of the cognition involved in self-knowledge.
This revised version was published online in June 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
14.
Spontaneously broken symmetries are often called hidden or secret symmetries. They are symmetries in the laws of nature that do not show up in observable phenomena. This raises the basic epistemological question: Is there reason to believe that these hidden symmetries are real features of nature rather than artifacts of theorizing. This paper clarifies the epistemic status of spontaneously broken symmetries. It presents the details of an argument by analogy that suggests the spontaneously broken gauge symmetry of electroweak interactions, and the subsequent hypothetico-deductive testing of the hypothesis. It is a story of how dubious means can lead to a credible end. 相似文献
15.
16.
17.
Jon Kenneth Newton 《Heythrop Journal》2018,59(4):733-746
Recent developments in Christian philosophy, in particular epistemology, need to be enriched by a study of epistemology in the Bible. This article uncovers the epistemological assumptions of the Book of Revelation (specifically related to spiritual experience, revelation, and eschatological vindication) and points out how they may advance the development of a contemporary Christian epistemology. 相似文献
18.
19.
Ram Neta 《Synthese》2006,150(2):247-280
Many epistemologists are interested in offering a positive account of how it is that many of our common sense beliefs enjoy
one or another positive epistemological status (e.g., how they are warranted, justified, reasonable, or what have you). A
number of philosophers, under the influence of Wittgenstein and/or J. L. Austin, have argued that this enterprise is misconceived.
The most effective version of this argument is to be found in Mark Kaplan’s paper “Epistemology on Holiday”. After explaining
what this criticism amounts to and why it is important, I then respond to it. My response is based upon, and is intended to
display the explanatory power of, a contractarian account of our practice of epistemic appraisal. 相似文献