共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Peter B. M. Vranas 《Journal of Philosophical Logic》2010,39(1):59-71
“Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight” is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an
imperative. Several philosophers, however (Williams 1963; Wedeking 1970; Harrison 1991; Hansen 2008), have denied that imperative
inferences exist, arguing that (1) no such inferences occur in everyday life, (2) imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions
of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, “since surrender” or “it follows that surrender or fight”, and
(3) distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions (“surrender or fight” permits you to fight without surrendering,
but “surrender” does not), so issuing distinct imperatives amounts to changing one’s mind and thus cannot be construed as
making an inference. In response I argue inter alia that, on a reasonable understanding of ‘inference’, some everyday-life
inferences do have imperatives as premises and conclusions, and that issuing imperatives with conflicting permissive presuppositions
does not amount to changing one’s mind. 相似文献
2.
Leon Horsten 《Synthese》1998,116(1):1-25
This paper presents a defense of Epistemic Arithmetic as used for a formalization of intuitionistic arithmetic and of certain
informal mathematical principles. First, objections by Allen Hazen and Craig Smorynski against Epistemic Arithmetic are discussed
and found wanting. Second, positive support is given for the research program by showing that Epistemic Arithmetic can give
interesting formulations of Church's Thesis.
This revised version was published online in June 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date. 相似文献
3.
The question of what means-and-ends structure our epistemic endeavors have is an important issue in recent epistemology, and is fundamental for understanding epistemic matters in principle. Crispin Sartwell has proposed arguments for the view that knowledge is our only ultimate goal, and justification is no part of it. An important argument is his instrumentality argument which is concerned with the conditions under which something could belong to our ultimate epistemic goal. Recently, this argument has been reconstructed and criticized by Pierre Le Morvan in a clear and helpful way. It will be shown, however, that Le Morvan’s criticism is not adequate, since it misconstrues the real instrumentality argument that can be found in Sartwell’s writings. 相似文献
4.
5.
6.
An immunizing strategy is an argument brought forward in support of a belief system, though independent from that belief system, which makes it more or less invulnerable to rational argumentation and/or empirical evidence. By contrast,
an epistemic defense mechanism is defined as a structural feature of a belief system which has the same effect of deflecting arguments and evidence. We discuss the remarkable recurrence of certain patterns of immunizing strategies and defense mechanisms in pseudoscience and other belief systems. Five different
types will be distinguished and analyzed, with examples drawn from widely different domains. The difference between immunizing
strategies and defense mechanisms is analyzed, and their epistemological status is discussed. Our classification sheds new
light on the various ways in which belief systems may achieve invulnerability against empirical evidence and rational criticism, and we propose our analysis as part of an explanation of these belief
systems’ enduring appeal and tenacity. 相似文献
7.
8.
9.
Irwin W. Silverman 《创造力研究杂志》2016,28(2):136-143
The hypothesis that pretend play facilitates the creative thought process in children has received a great deal of attention. In a literature review, Lillard et al. (2013, p. 8) concluded that the evidence for this hypothesis was “not convincing.” This article focuses on experimental and training studies that have tested this hypothesis. As categorized by Lillard et al., the majority of these studies failed to find evidence for the hypothesis. Furthermore, they contend that several of the studies that found evidence for the hypothesis were flawed either methodologically or statistically. This review of the evidence relative to this hypothesis included a larger number of studies, and, more important, screened studies for statistical power. The conclusion reached is that that the hypothesis is likely true. Additionally, it is shown that Lillard et al.’s criticisms of the studies that found evidence for the hypothesis do not stand up on close examination 相似文献
10.
11.
Loewy EH 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》2005,26(6):445-468
This paper argues that we have wrongly and not for the patient’s benefit made a form of stark autonomy our highest value which
allows physicians to slip out from under their basic duty which has always been to pursue a particular patient’s good. In
general – I shall argue – it is the patient’s right to select his or her own goals and the physician’s duty to inform the
patient of the feasibility of that goal and of the means needed to attain it. If the goal is not one that is possible, the
patient, with the physician and family, must select a feasible goal and then discuss the costs/benefits of various approaches.
The physician should take a leading role in helping the patient select the goal. I argue that to simply present a laundry
list of means and insist that patients choose for themselves is not only abandoning patients to their autonomy but is, in
fact, a crass form of violating the patient’s autonomy. Freely choosing not to choose is a choice a patient with decisional
capacity is entitled to make and one that needs to be respected. 相似文献
12.
13.
14.
15.
The sensitivity condition on knowledge says that one knows that P only if one would not believe that P if P were false. Difficulties
for this condition are now well documented. Keith DeRose has recently suggested a revised sensitivity condition that is designed
to avoid some of these difficulties. We argue, however, that there are decisive objections to DeRose’s revised condition.
Yet rather than simply abandoning his proposed condition, we uncover a rationale for its adoption, a rationale which suggests
a further revision that avoids our objections as well as others. The payoff is considerable: along the way to our revision,
we learn lessons about the epistemic significance of certain explanatory relations, about how we ought to envisage epistemic
closure principles, and about the epistemic significance of methods of belief formation. 相似文献
16.
17.
Rebecca Tuvel 《希帕蒂亚:女权主义哲学杂志》2017,32(2):263-278
Former NAACP chapter head Rachel Dolezal's attempted transition from the white to the black race occasioned heated controversy. Her story gained notoriety at the same time that Caitlyn Jenner 1 graced the cover of Vanity Fair, signaling a growing acceptance of transgender identity. Yet criticisms of Dolezal for misrepresenting her birth race indicate a widespread social perception that it is neither possible nor acceptable to change one's race in the way it might be to change one's sex. Considerations that support transgenderism seem to apply equally to transracialism. Although Dolezal herself may or may not represent a genuine case of a transracial person, her story and the public reaction to it serve helpful illustrative purposes. 相似文献
18.
Eric Mack 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》1999,2(2):87-115
This paper offers a programmatic philosophical articulation of moral and political individualism. This individualism consists of two main components: value individualism and rights individualism. The former is the view that, for each individual, the end which is of ultimate value is his own well-being. Each individual's well-being has ultimate agent-relative value and the only ultimate values are these agent-relative values. The latter view is that individuals possess moral jurisdiction over themselves, i.e., rights of self-ownership. These rights (along with other rights individuals may come to possess) constrain the manner in which agents may pursue value. For this reason, the articulated individualism is an constrained individualism. Sketches of arguments are offered for both value and rights individualism. And it is argued that the sole legitimate function of legal/political institutions is to further delineate and protect the rights of individuals. However, the paper is also concerned to indicate why this radical moral and political individualism does not have many of the features or implications that are commonly ascribed to it. In this connection, I seek to show how this social doctrine accords with individuals' having concern for the well-being of others, with the emergence of relationships among individuals that have both instrumental and non-instrumental value, with a degree of responsibility for self and others that is often thought to be antithetical to individualism and, in general, with a flourishing of civil order. 相似文献
19.