共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
Jonathan Knowles 《国际科学哲学研究》2002,16(2):171-186
The article presents a critical discussion of Larry Laudan's naturalistic metamethodological theory known as normative naturalism (NN). I examine the strongest extant objection to NN, and, with reference to ideas in Freedman ( Philosophy of Science , 66 (Proceedings), pp. S526-S537, 1999), show how NN survives it. I then go on to outline two problems that really do compromise NN. The first revolves around Laudan's conception of the relationship between scientific values and the history of science. Laudan argues we can make sense of progress in science without seeing great scientists in the past as having held the cognitive values and methodological rules we hold today as important for science. I argue this is extremely implausible, and moreover that Laudan must see our values today as justified by reference to the values of past scientists if he is to avoid a pernicious form of relativism. The second problem with NN is that its conception of methodological rules--as hypothetical imperatives linking cognitive means to ends--is untenable. Such rules would not be needed in a scientific community; moreover it is doubtful whether they should class as rules at all. I conclude by suggesting that the distinction between cognitive means and ends which undergirds Laudan's view is intuitively not well founded, and in any case does not provide sufficient materials for a viable normative naturalized epistemology. 相似文献
2.
Sally Shuttleworth 《Science as culture》2013,22(1):56-66
Bill Buford, ed., Granta 16: Science, London, Penguin, 1985, pb £3.95. 相似文献
3.
Neo‐Confucian epistemology and Chinese philosophy: Practical postulates for actioning psychology as a human science 下载免费PDF全文
James H. Liu 《Asian Journal of Social Psychology》2017,20(2):137-149
The world is growing more interconnected, and Asian societies are increasingly able to play leading roles in global society. However, Asian psychologists and social scientists have yet to draw from their cultural roots to create social sciences able to make a difference in their home societies. This paper articulates an epistemology for the aspirational practice of Height Psychology as a human science informed by Kantian epistemology in dialogue with other philosophies, especially Confucianism and Taoism. The possibility of ‘intellectual intuition’ (direct knowledge of thing‐in‐itself, or noumenon) is allowed in Eastern philosophical traditions that open a more agentic and human‐centred philosophy of science for action that goes beyond natural science epistemologies originating in Cartesian dualism. Kant's practical postulates are invoked to develop a moral and ethical philosophy that through civilizational dialogue can lead to a philosophy of science robustly incorporating culture and human agency. A thought experiment is offered where practical postulates of Chinese culture are held to be yin‐yang cosmology, human‐heartedness, and relationalism. It is argued that these facilitate an holistic science of practice that complements the sophistication of Western methods. Principles and an approach to theory‐building for human science are proposed. 相似文献
4.
5.
Daniel F. Hartner 《Philosophical Studies》2013,165(3):921-937
Three proponents of the Canberra Plan, namely Jackson, Pettit, and Smith, have developed a collective functionalist program—Canberra Functionalism—spanning from philosophical psychology to ethics. They argue that conceptual analysis is an indispensible tool for research on cognitive processes since it reveals that there are some folk concepts, like belief and desire, whose functional roles must be preserved rather than eliminated by future scientific explanations. Some naturalists have recently challenged this indispensability argument, though the point of that challenge has been blunted by a mutual conflation of metaphysical and methodological strands of naturalism. I argue that the naturalist’s challenge to the indispensability argument, like naturalism itself, ought to be reformulated as a strictly methodological thesis. So understood, the challenge succeeds by showing (1) that we cannot know a priori on the basis of conceptual analysis of folk platitudes that something must occupy the functional roles specified for beliefs and desires, and (2) that proponents of Canberra Functionalism sometimes tacitly concede this point by treating substantive psychological theories as the deliverances of a priori platitudes analysis. 相似文献
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
Philosophical Studies - This paper provides a new argument for the relevance of empirical research to moral and political philosophy and a novel defense of the positive program in experimental... 相似文献
11.
12.
13.
Dimiter Ginev 《Studies in Philosophy and Education》1990,10(1):63-71
This paper describes an attempt to develop a pedagogy for teaching philosophy in science rather than a philosophy of science to be taught in the Bulgarian educational system. 相似文献
14.
15.
16.
There has been a great deal of interest in the concept of luck in the recent psychological and philosophical literature. In philosophy, this interest has tended to focus not upon luck simpliciter but rather upon the role that luck plays in ethical and epistemological debates concerning (respectively) moral and epistemic luck. In psychology, in contrast, a number of studies have explicitly examined our everyday conceptions of luck and the manner in which these conceptions influence our lives. This article surveys both the recent psychological and philosophical literature on this topic and argues that (to different degrees) the work of both disciplines in this area has been hampered by a failure to be clearer about what luck involves. Accordingly, this article offers a specification of what is core to the notion of luck and highlights how this analysis can aid further research in this area by both psychologists and philosophers. 相似文献
17.
Elizabeth Potter 《Synthese》1995,104(3):423-439
I argue against the assumption that the influence of non-cognitive values must lead to bad science, opening the way for the thesis that non-cognitive values are compatible with good science. This, in turn, allows us to answer feminist questions, principally, How do gender politics influence science? without (1) having to reject the question a priori because theories of science assume that political values cannot influence good scientific work and (2) having made a case for the influence of gender politics upon a particular bit of scientific work, being put into the ludicrous position of saying that it is bad science after all, even though the relevant community of scientists say it is good. Nevertheless, moral and political neutrality is held to be a norm of good science and a tacit metaphilosophical norm governing good philosophy of science, viz., a good philosophy of science reveals and analyzes the morally and politically neutral production of good science. This metaphilosophical norm insures that the philosophy of science (1) is blind to the influence of non-cognitive values on good science if and when these are present and so (2) acquiesces in the moral or political arrangements supported by the science in question. 相似文献
18.
19.
Heather Douglas 《Synthese》2010,177(3):317-335
Philosophy of science was once a much more socially engaged endeavor, and can be so again. After a look back at philosophy
of science in the 1930s–1950s, I turn to discuss the current potential for returning to a more engaged philosophy of science.
Although philosophers of science have much to offer scientists and the public, I am skeptical that much can be gained by philosophers
importing off-the-shelf discussions from philosophy of science to science and society. Such efforts will likely look like
efforts to do applied ethics by merely applying ethical theories to particular contexts and problems. While some insight can
be gained by these kinds of endeavors, the most interesting and pressing problems for the actual practitioners and users of
science are rarely addressed. Instead, I recommend that philosophers of science engage seriously and regularly with scientists
and/or the users of science in order to gain an understanding of the conceptual issues on the ground. From such engagement,
flaws in the traditional philosophical frameworks, and how such flaws can be remedied, become apparent. Serious engagement
with the contexts of science thus provides the most fruit for philosophy of science per se and for the practitioners whom the philosophers aim to assist. And if one focuses on contexts where science has its most
social relevance, these efforts can help to provide the thing that philosophy of science now lacks: a full-bodied philosophy
of science in society. 相似文献